an international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume 15, Fall 2018, ISSN 1552-5112
The Poststructuralist Broom of Wallace’s System: A Conversation
Between Wittgenstein and Derrida
I.
Introduction
David
Foster Wallace famously characterized his first novel, The Broom of the System, as ‘a conversation between [Ludwig]
Wittgenstein and [Jacques] Derrida.’[1] This comes as little surprise,
given the ubiquity of the question of language in the works of these two
thinkers, and given the novel’s constant reflections on the relation between
language and world. Broom’s
protagonist, Lenore Beadsmen – in
search of her eponymous great-grandmother – is preoccupied with the dread that
‘all that really exists of [her] life is what can be said about it,’[2] that is to say, that reality
is entirely coextensive with
language. If, as Wittgenstein says, ‘The
limits of my language mean the limits of my world,’[3] and, ‘I am my world,’[4]
then it stands to reason that ‘the limits of my language mean the limits of
myself.’ This is the fearful
hypothesis that drives The Broom of the
System.
Much of the scholarship surrounding
the novel has interpreted Wallace’s remark as an assertion that the novel
constitutes a debate between
Wittgenstein and Derrida, and has, more often than not,
assumed that Wittgenstein ‘wins’ that debate for Wallace. In his groundbreaking
work, Understanding David Foster Wallace,
Marshall Boswell writes that for Wallace, ‘the job of the post-Barth [i.e., John Barth, with whom
Boswell lumps Derrida] novelist is to ‘… overturn the related insistence that
texts are “closed systems” that produce their own meaning through endless
self-reference.’ The ‘self-conscious meta-fictional novel,’ he writes, ‘in
David Foster Wallace’s hands, becomes an open system of communication—an
elaborate and entertaining game—between author and reader,’[5]
and Boswell credits Wittgenstein as the inspiration for this thought of the
open system. Alternatively, some scholars have left Derrida out of the
discussion entirely.[6] Despite the oft-cited
quotation from Lipsky’s book, it remains the case, as Bradley Fest has noted,
that Derrida’s ‘influence on Wallace’s work still remains largely unexplored.’[7]
There are a number
of likely explanations for this privileging of Wittgenstein. The most
obvious is the fact that Wallace himself addresses Wittgenstein far more
frequently and directly than he does Derrida. Wallace famously wrote a review
of David Markson’s Wittgenstein’s
Mistress, which includes a fair amount of broader commentary on
Wittgenstein’s project.[8]
While Derrida’s name does not appear in The
Broom of the System, Wittgenstein’s name is mentioned multiple times, as
the ‘mad crackpot genius’[9] who had been the inspiration
for Gramma Lenore’s philosophy, which is the source of Lenore’s aforementioned dread. Wittgenstein was the author of the Philosophical Investigations and of an
apparently esoteric green book without
which Gramma Lenore never left her home at the Shaker Heights nursing facility.[10] Indeed Wittgenstein,
represented by the ever-elusive Gramma Lenore herself, wafts like a specter
through the entirety of the novel. However, any simple valorization of
Wittgenstein in the thinking of Wallace risks overlooking what Wallace
characterizes as the ‘horror’ that Wittgenstein leaves us with.[11]
In the famous interview with Larry McCaffery, Wallace cites Wittgenstein as
‘the real architect of the postmodern trap,’[12]
the worry, indoctrinated into Lenore by her great-grandmother, that ‘a life is
words and nothing else,’ that there is no ‘extra-linguistic anything.’[13]
The dread that burdens Lenore also burdens
Wallace, and it is this dread for which Wallace seeks a solution in his
writing, both in The Broom of the System and
beyond. As Wallace says to McCaffery, ‘If the world is itself a linguistic
construct, there’s nothing “outside” language for language to have to picture
or refer to. This … leads right to the postmodern, poststructural
dilemma of having to deny yourself an existence independent of language.’[14] If the novel is indeed a
‘conversation between Wittgenstein and Derrida,’ and if it is Wittgenstein, and not Derrida, whose
thinking points toward the ‘postmodern trap,’ then perhaps we should consider
that Derrida may have been a source of hope for Wallace.
In this essay, I therefore invite
Derrida into this conversation, arguing that, contrary to popular intuitions,
Derrida might just be the thinker who points the way in Wallace’s system beyond
the ‘postmodern trap.’ As noted, Wallace grapples with the ‘horror’ of language
with no ‘outside’. We can think of this ‘anxiety of the outside’ in two ways:
(1) that my language belongs only to me,
and so if there is no outside of language, there is no outside of myself – the problem of solipsism from
the early Wittgenstein, about which Wallace worried extensively; (2) that the world itself is nothing more than
language, and hence there is no outside of language that would constitute myself, nothing more to me than the language that is used to
describe me – I am not truly a self at
all. As Lenore’s significant other – Rick Vigorous – says of Lenore, ‘she
simply felt … as if she had no real existence…’[15]
It is Derrida – the silent interlocutor in the book – and not Wittgenstein, who
disrupts this double bind, with his famous ‘non-concept’ known as différance, the differential play of force at the
heart of all language (and life). Différance points
toward an essential exteriority at the heart of the self, thereby avoiding the
solipsistic danger of the self-enclosed world. Moreover, différance also points toward an
essential outside to language,
according to Derrida, and in so doing, it points toward dimensions of human
life – intensity, desire, affect, force – that elude the grasp of language,
precisely because they too are part of the differential play. Before addressing
these characteristics of différance, I shall first discuss Wallace’s
anxiety of the outside through the ‘double bind’ he sees in Wittgenstein.
II.
Wittgenstein and the ‘Double Bind’ of
Language
The early Wittgenstein, seeking to resolve the
inherited problems of the Western philosophical tradition, attempts to
determine the limits of, as well as the relations between, thought, logic,
language, and the world. Beginning from the claim that ‘The world is all that
is the case,’[16] Wittgenstein then asserts that ‘The world is the
totality of facts, not of things.’[17] With this claim, Wittgenstein makes an ontological
assertion regarding an epistemic principle – the ‘world’ is not a collection of
objects, but rather, a collection of facts, or states of affairs.
These facts are represented in the form of propositions,[18] and propositions – if well formulated – break down atomistically in such a way as to isomorphically
mirror their corresponding states of affairs,[19] and ‘The totality of propositions is language.’[20] Since language is logically structured, so too is
the world, and language and the world, for Wittgenstein, share the same logical
structure. But as we have seen, the world is all that is the case. This
leads to a horrifying problem. The language of any given individual will
necessarily be limited by the fact that she is a finite being, with finite
capacities for knowledge, and hence, a finite grasp of the language that
pictures the world for her. But she is not capable of transcending the
language whereby she structures the world, because the very mechanism with which
she would do so (i.e., language), is limited in her own specific ways.
And since language structures what we think, and ‘We cannot think what we
cannot think,’[21] it follows that language acts as a rigid boundary
of my experience of the world, which is, as far as is available to me, the
world itself. Hence, as we have seen, ‘The limits of my language mean
the limits of my world,’[22] and Wittgenstein goes on to say that ‘The world is my
world,’[23] arguing that there is truth to the claims of the
solipsist. We should note, moreover, that philosophical solipsism of the sort
that Wittgenstein theorizes, though seemingly absurd, is difficult to argue
one’s way out of: as Anscombe writes, ‘It is difficult to get rid of such a
conception once one has it.’[24] Wallace refers to Wittgenstein’s solipsism as ‘a
real Book-of-Genesis-type tragic fall. The ‘loss of the whole external world,’[25] and it is, in a sense, the position against which
Wallace spends his entire life writing.
In
shifting from the apparently private, solipsistic language of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
to the language-games model of the Philosophical Investigations,
Wittgenstein begins to emphasize the intrinsically communal aspects of
language, a shift that Wallace himself acknowledges and affirms: ‘Wittgenstein
argues that for language even to be possible, it must always be a function of
relationships between persons…’[26] Marshall Boswell acknowledges this communal
function as well, writing that ‘A language-game in Wittgenstein must be played
by more than one participant…’[27] However, Boswell then goes further, writing, ‘The
point here is that for Wittgenstein, language does not displace us from the
world but rather takes place “in” that world, specifically among people in
language-game situations.’[28] The key here, and the point with which I am not
confident Wallace would agree, is Boswell’s assertion that language takes
place in the world – this ‘in’ amounts to a distinction between language
and the world. Wallace almost seems to explicitly reject this point, at least
as it pertains to Wittgenstein. For Wallace, Wittgenstein’s shift from the Tractatus to the Investigations indeed
points to a solution to the Tractarian problem of solipsism, but it does so by
essentially expanding the language of the individual to the language of the
community – the limits of the private world simply become the limits of
the communal world. What Wittgenstein’s shift does not do,
according to Wallace, is alter the view that the world is itself linguistic.
This passage bears a lengthy citation:
‘This was Wittgenstein’s double bind: you can
either treat language as an infinitely small dense dot, or you let it become
the world—the exterior and everything in it. The former banishes you from the
Garden. The latter seems more promising. If the world is itself a linguistic
construct, there’s nothing “outside” language for language to have to picture
or refer to. This lets you avoid solipsism, but it leads right to the
postmodern, poststructural dilemma of having to deny
yourself an existence independent of language. Heidegger’s the guy most people
think got us into this bind, but when I was working on Broom of the System I saw Wittgenstein as the real architect of the
postmodern trap. He died right on the edge of explicitly treating reality as
linguistic instead of ontological. This eliminated solipsism, but not the
horror. Because we’re still stuck. … If I were separate from language, if I
could somehow detach from it and climb up and look down on it, get the lay of
the land so to speak, I could study it “objectively,” take it apart,
deconstruct it, know its operations and boundaries and deficiencies. But that’s
not how things are. I’m in it. We’re in language.’[29]
Just
prior to this, Wallace says that ‘we’re stuck in here, in language, even if
we’re at least all in here together.’[30] This passage of text reflects
Wallace’s understanding of the two modes of the ‘anxiety of the outside,’
mentioned above: at one pole, the problem of solipsism; and at the other pole,
the fear that the world itself, and my life with it, are nothing more than
words – the infinitely small dense dot versus
the exterior and everything in it.
But it must be noted, Wallace ascribes both of these modes to Wittgenstein; Wittgenstein does not
get us out of them. Contrary to Boswell, on Wallace’s understanding of
Wittgenstein’s later philosophy, language is not in the world; language is
the world. The all-consuming capacity of language is embodied in Broom by Norman Bombardini,
whose ‘Project Total Yang,’[31] the goal of which is to
consume the entire universe, ‘literalizes the option’[32] of the pervasiveness of
language, the linguistic exhaustibility of the world, according to Wallace.
Given that the ubiquity of the
linguistic construct is the primary concern of Broom, and given that Wallace clearly associates this worry with
Wittgenstein, the question then becomes, where is Derrida in this so-called
‘conversation’? It is worth noting, the assumption of the ubiquity of language
or of the world as nothing but language and texts, is a view often casually
(and carelessly) ascribed to Derrida himself. Clayton Crockett speaks
critically of such interpretations of Derrida as ‘some late-twentieth-century
linguistic idealism and subjectivist constructivism that just plays with
language.’[33]
From Derrida’s famously provocative and notoriously untranslatable formulation,
‘Il n’y a pas
de hors texte,’[34] (rendered subtly by Gayatri
Spivak as ‘There is nothing outside of
the text’ and as ‘there is no outside-text’),[35]
we get John Searle’s bastardization, ‘There exists nothing outside of texts,’[36] a forceful misreading
(pluralizing a singular noun to amplify its effect) designed to commit Derrida
to the position that the only things
that exist are words and texts. But the sinister aura surrounding Derrida
extends far beyond the ivory towers of academic philosophy to the culture writ
large, and many scholars outside of philosophy departments associate the most
pernicious forms of an ill-defined postmodernism with Derrida. Indeed, Boswell
writes of Derrida that ‘Amid all this multiplicity and fecundity, however, the
one thing that is lost is the world itself; rather, the text displaces the
outside world in exchange for the self-referential universe of signs.’[37]
But Wallace explicitly ascribes this view to Wittgenstein – not to Derrida – so
if Broom really is a conversation between Derrida and
Wittgenstein, it would seem Derrida would have to contribute something other than this, as a basic feature of
any ‘conversation’ is that both interlocutors contribute something.
This brings us to the title of the
novel – The Broom of the System. An
onion of significance, the title reportedly refers to the phrase that Wallace’s
mother used to describe roughage;[38]
it nominally refers to an example used in Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations;[39] and in Broom, the broom story is used to illustrate Wittgenstein’s claim
that ‘the meaning of a word is its use in the language.’[40] Lenore’s father tells her the
story of when, as a child, his grandmother, Lenore Sr., sat him in the kitchen
and questioned him about which part of the broom were ‘more elemental, more fundamental,’[41]
the bristles or the handle. He responded that the bristles were more essential,
because one could sweep by hand, using only the bristles, but could not do so
using only the handle. Her father then says:
‘…she tackled me, and
knocked me out of my chair, and yelled into my ear something like, “Aha, that’s because you want to sweep with the broom, isn’t it? It’s
because of what you want the broom for,
isn’t it?” Et cetera. And that if what we wanted a broom for was to break
windows, then the handle was clearly
the fundamental essence of the broom, and she illustrated with the kitchen
window, and a crowd of domestics gathered; but that if we wanted the broom to
sweep with, see for example the broken glass, sweep sweep,
the bristles were the thing’s essence.’[42]
This
example, however, does not merely illustrate
Wittgenstein’s point about ‘meaning as use’. Any number of examples could be
adduced to support this principle – for instance, if using a credit card to
shop, the numbers are the essence;
however, if trying to jimmy a lock, the physical
card itself – its specific size, shape, and thickness – is essential. More
precisely, what makes the broom example so interesting is that the meanings of
the broom are oppositional in nature; the very structure whereby we purify, (removing the foreign particles
of glass from the floor), is also that whereby we contaminate – the thing that cleans the mess is also the very thing
that created the mess in the first place.
Furthermore, the concept of the
‘system’ plays an important role in the novel, as Lenore cites Gramma Lenore as
saying that ‘Every telling creates and limits and defines,’ and that ‘any
telling automatically becomes a kind of system, that controls everybody
involved.’[43]
Moreover, there are multiple references throughout the novel to the concept of
the self, and questions of whether the self is merely a node in a system or network, or whether the self is itself a
system, in relation with other systems.[44]
The system is a linguistic construct, and the broom in the novel plays a
dually, constituting-shattering role in that construct. It is this bifurcation
of meaning that here interests me. Like Derrida’s ‘non-concept’ of différance, the broom both enables and disables;
it purifies and impurifies. Let us now turn to a discussion of Derrida’s différance.
III.
Derrida and the Non-Concept of Différance
Derrida
creates the concept of différance
as a way of addressing foundational philosophical problems that he discovers in
the course of his nearly two decades spent immersed in the work of Edmund
Husserl, founder of the monumentally important, early twentieth-century
philosophical movement known as phenomenology. At the core of Husserl’s project
is the necessity to examine the essences and meaning-making structures of
consciousness, because the constitution of meaning lies at the basis of all
human knowledge, and like his intellectual forebear – René Descartes – Husserl
seeks to once again restore philosophy to its ‘rightful place’ as the ground,
or the queen, of the sciences. Borrowing language from Heidegger, we can say
that philosophy for Husserl is to be the fundamental ontology on which are to
be based all other ‘regional’ ontologies. Also like
Descartes, Husserl wants to abolish every shred of uncertainty in this
endeavor, so that philosophy can be the quintessentially rigorous science. But
so long as there is mediation or interpretation of any sort involved in the
constitution of knowledge, the assurance of certainty is precarious. With this in mind, Husserl performs a series of
philosophical ‘reductions’ whereby he ‘brackets’ (or puts in suspension) all
questions concerning the so-called ‘reality’ of both the external world, and
the psychological ego with which it interacts, isolating the ‘transcendental
ego’[45]
– a purely interior sphere of analysis, uncontaminated by any externals, and
unmediated by any foreign consciousnesses. Here we should note the parallels
between the problems of Husserl and Derrida and those of Lenore, specifically
that, in both cases, the fundamental problem is the question of how and where
to locate the truest identity of the ‘self.’
Any passage of time within this
interiority brings the issue of memory into
play, insofar as the self-who-now-is must, in a sense, relate to a
self-who-is-no-more, a past self. Even this seemingly insignificant gap in the
experience constitutes mediation, and thereby compromises the attainment of
certainty on the part of the subject. Simply put, memory is notoriously
unreliable. Therefore, Husserl’s emphasis on pure, unmediated interiority
depends upon an atomistic punctuatedness of the
‘now,’ an at least ideal moment of impression as a
discrete and self-contained nucleus of time and experience. However, beginning
in 1905, Husserl began formulating a component of his philosophy that would be
central to his thought for the rest of his life – an essential framework of
internal time-consciousness known as the ‘living present,’[46]
designed to provide a phenomenologically or experientially faithful account of
the subject’s relation to time. The living present consists of the atomized
now-point, referred to as the ‘primal impression,’ and also
contains as a structural component a mode known as ‘retention,’ a
non-representational memory of a previous
impression, still living and still attached to the current impression. One of Husserl’s favorite examples to
illuminate this structure is the experience of listening to a piece of music.
To truly hear a song as a song (as notes and tones in
sequence and relation with each other) requires that, in addition to the sound
we are currently hearing, we have a memory
of the preceding series of notes; otherwise, we would hear only a random,
discontinuous series of discrete sounds, not a song. Moreover, the memory required in order to hang onto these
notes is not forceful or deliberate; without trying, without intentionally
representing the notes to ourselves, our consciousness hangs onto them.
At the nexus of these two equally
important Husserlian impetuses – (the discrete punctuatedness of the now, and the comet’s tail of
retention) – Derrida discovers an essential and irreducible tension. The
necessities of Husserl’s project – which, for Derrida, embodies the ‘most
modern, critical, and vigilant form’[47]
of Western metaphysics – dictate that the moment of impression is to be purely
interior, unmediated, and hence, related to no
outside whatsoever – the primal impression must be the punctuated
source-point and the causa sui wellspring of what will become, a posteriori,
the retention. However, the fact that
Husserl’s comprehensive model of time-consciousness is itself an essential and
ideal structure entails that whatever
is stamped in the impression will necessarily, i.e., a priori, be retained; and this means that it must already be
repeatable, prior to its being impressed,
and as a condition of its being
impressed in the first place. If the content is not repeatable, it will not be
retained; but given the essential ideality of the time-consciousness structure,
it will be retained; therefore, it must be repeatable. Rather than the
impression being the condition of repetition, with the repetition being a
secondary and deficient copy of the ‘first’, Derrida’s analyses of Husserl
demonstrate that repetition is the
condition of impression; repetition is ‘present’ already in the impression.
But since, all along, we were seeking the punctuated, purely interior and
unmediated nucleus of time as the core of the ego, we can now see that, despite
Husserl’s efforts, this interiority or ‘presence’ is only possible by relating
to an outside, or ‘non-presence.’ Derrida writes, ‘This relation to
non-presence, once more, does not take by surprise, surround, or even
dissimulate the presence of the originary impression;
it allows its upsurge and its ever reborn virginity.’[48] This relationality or
repetition is essential, not accidental, and this relationality – productive
and creative – is what Derrida refers to under the name of différance. Derrida writes that
‘the possibility of re-petition in its most general form, the trace in the most
universal sense, is a possibility that not only must inhabit the pure actuality
of the now, but must also constitute it by means of
the very movement of the différance that the
possibility inserts into the pure actuality of the now.’ A few lines later, he
writes that ‘the concept of pure solitude … is split open by its own origin, by the very condition of its
self-presence.’[49] Put more simply, Derrida
argues that the outside is the
condition of the inside, that to be a
self requires a relation to otherness, but an otherness at the heart
of self-identity. Like the G.O.D. in Broom,
the ‘Other for Ohio’s Self,’[50]
or the fact that Lenore is searching for Lenore, and in so doing, is searching
for herself, there is always an otherness at the heart of self-identity,
and this is predicated upon the productive play of force that Derrida calls différance. Let
us now look at how Derrida’s contribution operates in The Broom of the System.
IV.
Somewhere Outside the Double Bind
Différance, Derrida
writes, is the ‘“active,” moving discord of different forces,’[51] and ‘the non-full, non-simple,
structured and differentiating origin of differences.’[52] Force, the play of which
constitutes différance,
is, Derrida says, ‘the other of language without which language would not be
what it is.’[53]
‘…[E]very process of signification,’ he writes, is ‘a formal play of
differences. That is, of traces.’[54] There are two very important
implications of this structure. First, because this play of force is in play, it not only makes meaning possible; it also essentially ensures
slippages of meaning such that language can never completely secure the stasis
of signification that it desires. The differential play that enables
meaning-making and communication also ensures failure – not as an empirical accident of language, but as part of its
nature. The second implication of différance is the following: the conditions of
signification[55]
that make language possible cannot themselves be put into words. Force is the basis of language, and it is the outside of language. This
is why, vexing though it may be to some of Derrida’s critics (and even
some of his most loyal fans), Derrida’s own descriptions are frequently so
non-committal. Différance, as he says, is ‘neither a word nor a
concept’[56] and ‘is never presented as
such.’[57]
[58] But
the corollary is the acknowledgement that, if the conditions of meaningfulness
cannot be put into words, it is because a vast portion of intensive, affective
life lies beyond the grasp of language. Call it ‘mystical’ if you like.
Language may be the only descriptive, explanatory mechanism we have to grasp these dimensions of life, but it is
insufficient. Indeed, Wittgenstein himself appears to acknowledge this
principle, even if he does not provide the ‘ultra-transcendental’[59] concepts to foster the
thinking of it: ‘There are, indeed, things that cannot be put into words. They make themselves manifest. They are what
is mystical.’[60] The primary reason that
Derrida appears to be the more instrumental of Wallace’s two interlocutors is
that both of these features of différance can be seen on display throughout The Broom of the System. Let’s look first at the breakdowns of language.
We must keep in mind that the
fearful hypothesis of The Broom of the
System is that ‘…life is what can be said about it,’[61]
or that reality is coextensive with and exhausted by language. But in the novel we see language fail in a number of very important
ways. First, we see failure on the part of speakers. In
particular, we see failure in the oversaturation of signification, as
when David Bloemker – Administrator of the nursing
facility – announces to Lenore that her great-grandmother is the ringleader of
the facility’s residents:
‘There is in addition
the fact that the resident whose temporary unavailability is relevant to you,
that is to say, Lenore, enjoyed a status here—with the facility administration,
the staff, and, through the force of her personality and her evident gifts,
especially with the other residents—that leads one to believe that, were the mislocation a result of anything other than outright
coercion on the part of some outside person or persons, which seems unlikely,
it would not be improper to posit the location and retrieval of Lenore as near
assurance of retrieving the other misplaced parties.’[62]
When
Lenore says to Bloemker, ‘I didn’t understand any of
that,’ his response is simply, ‘Your great-grandmother was
more or less the ringleader around here.’ Now, if the fearful hypothesis
were correct – that reality is coextensive with language – then it would seem that the more
language one used to describe a
fact about the world, the more real or
the more understood the fact would be.
Wallace, however, demonstrates that this is not necessarily true. Our failure
to understand Bloemker’s very simple point does not
reside in the mere vocabulary – each individual word of the sentence is
comprehensible to most English-speaking adults with at least a secondary
education. Moreover, the sentence is grammatically correct. The breakdown
occurs because of the sheer oversaturation of language; this excess of signification actually results in a breakdown or incapacity of
interpretation.
Likewise, we see the failures of
language in the opposite direction, where a proposition, meaningful on its
face, lacks any locutionary intention or context, but is interpreted by the listener as oversaturated with
signification. This type of failure is most evident in Lenore’s loquacious
cockatiel, Vlad the Impaler. Having apparently been fed the experimental
cattle-endocrine-derivative-infused Stonecipheco baby
food, Vlad suddenly begins to speak, at first mimicking the vulgar and sexually
charged words of Lenore’s roommate, Candy. Lenore, fearing the wrath of the
landlady in the event she were to hear Vlad’s
utterances, begins reciting passages from the Bible for him to memorize. The
sensationalist televangelist, Reverend Sykes, later interprets Vlad’s words as
‘a manifestation of the earthly intervention and influence of the Almighty
comparable in significance to the weeping fir tree of Yrzc,
Poland, and the cruciform tar-pit formations of Sierra Leone!’[63]
Later, when Sykes has made Vlad (renamed as Ugolino
the Significant) the co-host of his ‘Partners With God Club’ television
program, we see Sykes expanding upon Vlad’s meaningless utterances, conveying
them to his viewers as touched by the hand of God. In one particularly
interesting exchange, Vlad, repeating a line from Candy’s earlier break-up
speech rehearsal says, ‘You fill me up. You satisfy me like no man did before.
I can’t deny it. God.’[64] Sykes then ‘interprets’ this
line for his viewers in the following way: ‘Yes friends I stand before you on
national prime-time television
talking about the satisfaction of
your every need. The fulfillment of
your every wish.’[65] There are several other
examples of this overinterpretation of Vlad’s meaningless words on the part of
Reverend Sykes. Vlad’s utterances are words, every bit as much as they were
when Candy spoke them, but they are little more than hollow shells, lacking
significance, until they are laced with the overwrought interpretations of
Sykes, fed to a spiritually bankrupt viewership.
Now, let us look at the ways in
which the novel points to aspects of life that are unencapsulable by language,
the second implication of Derridean différance, evident in a few key passages. The first is
where Rick is attempting to coerce Lenore into saying the words, ‘I love you.’
Rick, sensing Lenore’s reticence at using the word ‘love’ to characterize her
feelings, says, ‘Some words have to be explicitly uttered, Lenore. Only by actually uttering certain words does one really do what one says. “Love” is one of those words, performative words. Some words
can literally make things real.’[66] A ‘performative’ is, as Rick
says, a word or proposition the truth of which is established in its utterance.
Examples include a clergy person’s proclamation that ‘I now pronounce you
husband and wife,’ a person’s saying, ‘I promise,’ or a parent’s saying,
‘You’re grounded.’ These phrases become true,
in virtue of the fact that the person uttering them possesses the authority to make them true on the basis of their utterance alone. Rick then goes on to
demand of Lenore that she list in detail the exact characteristics of Rick’s
personality that she loves: ‘I need to know, so that I might try desperately to
reinforce those features of me on the basis of which
you love me. So that I can have you inside myself, for all time.’[67] Leaving aside the disturbingly
possessive elements of Rick’s demand, his insistence raises an interesting
problem/question. If the fearful hypothesis at the root of Gramma Lenore’s
philosophy – that the world is nothing more than language – were indeed
correct, then not only is Rick correct, that some words are performatives; rather, it is one hundred percent the
case that all words are
performatives. If reality is only linguistic, then nothing is true unless it
is put into words. Likewise, this being the case, it would also follow that
love, being only what can be said, would have to correspond to or fixate upon
characteristics that are themselves linguistically formulated. In other words,
if Gramma Lenore is right, then Rick is right as well, and love just is what we can say about it. This
is why Lenore says to Rick, ‘You and Gramma Lenore should get together, is who
should get together.’[68]
So if the fearful hypothesis were true, then Lenore should be persuaded by
Rick’s pleas; but what is interesting is that she’s not.
Lenore goes on to characterize love
in a way that denies outright that it can be truly characterized by language,
saying to Rick, ‘I think you and I maybe just have a different conception of
this, you know, this “love” thing.’[69] She
goes on to describe love – deep and meaningful love – as a sort of ‘reversal,’
wherein we first experience attraction to another person on the basis of
defined characteristics, such as their physical appearance, their intelligence,
their personality, or some specific combination of some of these or other
features. But as that attraction grows into affection, and we cross the
threshold into loving the person, ‘everything sort of
reverses. It’s not that you love the person because of certain things anymore;
it’s that you love the things about the person because you love the person. It kind of radiates out, instead of in.’[70]
Not only can Lenore not say exactly what ‘love’ is, it is further the case that
she cannot conceive of love as corresponding to a set of identifiable
(nameable) characteristics about a person. In every way, language falls short
of the task of characterizing love. Hence, in this passage, we see that Lenore
cannot possibly subscribe to Gramma Lenore’s theory, the fearful hypothesis,
that ‘all that really exists of my life is what can be said about it.’[71]
Language fails.
We see language fail in this way
again in the episode that takes place between Lenore and Andy Lang as they lay
on Lang’s bed:
‘Lenore and Wang-Dang
Lang were on Lang’s bed, on their sides, facing each other, amid shirts and
socks in their plastic wrappers. Lenore had on her bra and panties and socks;
Lang had on just his chinos and belt. Lenore’s legs were together, and Lang had
one of his legs thrown over her hip. Lang was looking at Lenore’s breasts, in
her bra. Being on her side was pressing them together, and they were pushing
partway over the bra, which Lang obviously liked. He looked at Lenore, and touched her. He rubbed the back of her neck for
her. And from time to time he would trace lines on her body with his finger. He
would trace a line down the center of her lips, her chin, her throat, and down
the line where her breasts pressed together, and over the bottom of the bra,
and onto her stomach, where his hand would spread out and cover her, making
Lenore need to blink, every time. He would also shift a bit and trace the line
where her legs pressed together, from the bottom of her panties to the tops of
her knees. He would press his finger deep into the line between her legs, and
Lenore knew her legs felt soft and hot to him, from being pressed together.
Lang had an erection in his slacks, Lenore could tell.’[72]
What’s
happening in this passage feels out of keeping with much of the rest of the
novel’s zany Pynchonesque nomenclature and
meandering, conspiratorial plots. The passage says a great deal. But it is even
more interesting for what it does not say.
It is a purely external description of the event, making no pretense at
describing the internal states or affects of the two
participants. More than anything else, particularly in what remains of the
passage, what is described are the words and actions of the two, but no effort is made, either on the part of the
characters themselves or of the narrator, to characterize their feelings. But
it does not matter. The reader knows what
they are feeling, without having it described to them. No person above a
certain age, no one who has ever felt the pangs of desire, or who has ever
brushed a finger across the near-naked flesh of their beloved, or had their
beloved brush their skin in this way, or been vulnerable in this way with
another human being; no one who has ever been in a similar situation in life is
without a clear sense of what Lang and Lenore are feeling. But Wallace does not
put it into words; nor would his trying to
put it into words be likely to succeed. Sexual arousal is not reducible to the
conjunction of the words ‘sexual’ and ‘arousal’, or to the word ‘erection’ as
it appears in the text. And not even what we call ‘sexual’ arousal aptly
encapsulates what is taking place between the lines of this passage, because we
know that it is not merely the mechanical impulse for reproduction, but an
ineffable, dare I say mystical, confluence of excitement, sexuality,
transgression, anxiety, tenderness, compassion, and so on, none of which aptly
characterizes any single component of the experience. Language fails in this
case. It fails not because of an oversaturation of signification on the part of
the speaker, or because of an overinterpretation on the part of the listener,
as in the cases we saw above. Rather, language fails because it is bound by
static categories, and of its very nature it tries to fix, to freeze, to hold
still, what can only be understood in terms of intensity, affect, or force. It
fails because force is the other of language, its outside; and force, as well
as its intensive plays that often go under the insufficient names of intensity,
affect, and desire, constitute us and arguably the vast
majority of our lives. It fails because there are innumerable aspects of
the human experience that cannot be characterized linguistically. They are, as
Wittgenstein says, ‘the mystical.’ The
Broom of the System seems, like Derrida’s différance, to point toward an
essential outside to language, in the
form of force and intensity. We are not merely linguistic, because language
itself is the product of plays of force, which also express themselves in and
through our being.
V.
Conclusion
In
this way, though his name never appears in The
Broom of the System, it is Derrida, and not Wittgenstein, who points beyond
the double bind that we characterized above as the ‘anxiety of the outside.’
If, as Wittgenstein thought, ‘The limits
of my language mean the limits of my world,’[73]
and, ‘I am my world,’[74]
the implication is that I am nothing more than the language used, by myself or
others, to characterize me – my life is purely linguistic. In its most
horrifying form, my
language is specific to me, and I am trapped alone, forever inside my own head,
the infinitely small dense dot. Wittgenstein corrected this problem with his
communal notion of the language-game, but in doing so, he left untouched,
according to Wallace, the principle that the world itself, and everything in
it, is linguistic. I am, as Wallace dreaded, ‘stuck.’ When we take more
seriously Wallace’s remarks to Lipsky about The
Broom of the System as a conversation between Wittgenstein and Derrida, it
seems clear that Derrida’s is the voice that offers Wallace a way out of the
double bind. First, as différance
illustrates that the self is always constituted by a relation to the outside,
there can be no absolute limit drawn to the ‘I’ to constitute a solipsistic
microcosm. On this, (the later) Wittgenstein and Derrida agree. Second, given
that this differential play of force operates outside the limits of language, as the other of language for Derrida, it cannot be the case that the world
is merely a linguistic construct. On the contrary, the forces of thought that
make up the movements of signification whereby language becomes possible are in
commerce with the affective and intensive forces that make up the flows of the
world and of our very lives. As The Broom of the
System attempts to signal, there are countless aspects of the human
experience that lie beyond the reach of language. Thus, despite Wallace’s
assertion that ‘there’s a lot of stuff in that novel I’d like to reel back in
and do better,’[75] The Broom of the System appears to succeed in characterizing,
through extensive engagement with certain dangerous temptations of language,
‘what it is to be a fucking human being.’[76]
an international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume 15, Fall 2018,
ISSN 1552-5112
NOTES
[1] David Lipsky, Although of Course You End Up Becoming Yourself: A Road Trip with David Foster Wallace (New York: Broadway Books, 2010), 35.
[2] David Foster Wallace, The Broom of the System (New York: Penguin, 1987), 119. Hereafter referred to as ‘Broom’.
[3] Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. D.F. Pears and B.F. McGuinness (London and New York: Routledge, 1961), 5.6. (References to the Tractatus will hereafter refer to ‘Tractatus,’ and will use Wittgenstein’s propositional numbering).
[4] Tractatus, 5.63.
[5] Marshall Boswell, Understanding David Foster Wallace (Columbia: The University of South Carolina Press, 2003), 31. Lance Olsen, as well, in what was for a time the main scholarly piece on Broom, argues in favor of a Wittgensteinian approach. See Lance Olsen, ‘Termite Art, or Wallace’s Wittgenstein,’ Review of Contemporary Fiction 13, no. 2 (Summer 1993), 199-215.
[6] See also Patrick O’Donnell, ‘Almost a Novel: The Broom of the System,’ in ed. Marshall Boswell and Stephen J. Burn, A Companion to David Foster Wallace Studies (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013), 1-22.
[7] Bradley Fest, ‘“Then Out of the Rubble”: David Foster Wallace’s Early Fiction’, in ed. Marshall Boswell, David Foster Wallace and ‘The Long Thing’: New Essays on the Novels (New York and London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2014), 85-105; 87.
[8] David Foster Wallace, ‘The Empty Plenum: David Markson’s Wittgenstein’s Mistress,’ in Both Flesh and Not: Essays (New York: Back Bay Books, 2012), 73-116.
[9] Broom, 73.
[10] See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 3rd edition trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1953). This ‘green book’ almost certainly hearkens to the famous Blue and Brown Books, which formed the gestational philosophical reflections that later went into Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. See Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books, 2nd ed., (Oxford: Blackwell, 1960). This reference appears in Broom, 40.
[11] Larry McCaffery, ‘An Expanded Interview with David Foster Wallace,’ in ed. Stephen J. Burn, Conversations with David Foster Wallace (Jackson: University Press of Mississippi, 2012), 21-52; 45.
[12] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 45.
[13] Broom, 120-121.
[14] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 45.
[15] Broom, 67.
[16] Tractatus, 1.
[17] Tractatus, 1.1.
[18] Tractatus, 4.1.
[19] Tractatus, 4.04.
[20] Tractatus, 4.001.
[21] Tractatus, 5.61.
[22] Tractatus, 5.6.
[23] Tractatus, 5.62.
[24] G.E.M. Anscombe, An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus (London: Hutchinson University Library, 1959), 168.
[25] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 44.
[26] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 44. For this reason, I cannot agree with Bradley J. Fest when he writes that ‘For the Wallace of Broom, Wittgenstein’s thinking in The Philosophical Investigations has unintended apocalyptic implications: namely, the horrors of complete solipsism.’ Fest, “Then Out of the Rubble,” 89.
[27] Boswell, Understanding David Foster Wallace, 29.
[28] Boswell, Understanding David Foster Wallace, 30-31.
[29] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 45.
[30] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 44.
[31] Broom, 91.
[32] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 45.
[33] Clayton Crockett, Derrida After the End of Writing: Political Theology and New Materialism (New York: Fordham University Press, 2018), 1.
[34] Jacques Derrida, De la grammatologie, (Paris: Éditions de Minuit, 1967), 227.
[35] Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974), 158.
[36] John Searle, Mind, Language, and Society: Philosophy in the Real World (New York: Basic Books, 19). This is an extraordinarily poor translation of this passage.
[37] Boswell, Understanding David Foster Wallace, 30.
[38] Hugh Kennedy and Geoffrey Polk, ‘Looking for a Garde of Which to be Avant: An Interview with David Foster Wallace,’ in Conversations with David Foster Wallace, 11-20; 12.
[39] Philosophical Investigations, 60.
[40] Philosophical Investigations, 43.
[41] Broom, 149.
[42] Broom, 150.
[43] Broom, 122.
[44] See Broom, 344, 351.
[45] For a critical analysis of this transcendental ego, it is difficult to beat Jean-Paul Sartre’s The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness, trans. Forrest Williams and Robert Kirkpatrick (New York: Hill and Wang, 1989).
[46] See Edmund Husserl, Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (1893-1917). Husserliana Band X (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1992); trans. John Barnett Brough, On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893-1917) (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992).
[47] Jacques Derrida, Positions, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981), 4-5.
[48] Jacques Derrida, Voice and Phenomenon, trans. Leonard Lawlor (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2011), 56.
[49] Derrida, Voice and Phenomenon, 58-59.
[50] Broom, 54. See also, Vernon W. Cisney, ‘In G.O.D. We Trust: The Desert of the Religious in The Broom of the System, in ed. Martin Brick and Michael McGowan, Both Fiction and Not: The Religious Worlds of David Foster Wallace (forthcoming, Bloomsbury Academic Publishing).
[51] Jacques Derrida, Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982),18.
[52] Derrida, Margins of Philosophy, 11.
[53] Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), 27.
[54] Derrida, Positions, 26.
[55] Or ‘meaningfulness’.
[56] Derrida, Margins of Philosophy, 3.
[57] Derrida, Margins of Philosophy, 6.
[58] This is because ‘words’ are linguistic constructs that designate specific contents, typically understood as ‘concepts’, but the concepts themselves are fleshed out using the signs of language, all of which is made possible by what Derrida calls différance.
[59] Derrida, Voice and Phenomenon, 13.
[60] Tractatus, 6.522.
[61] David Foster Wallace, The Broom of the System (New York: Penguin, 1987), 119. Hereafter referred to as ‘Broom’.
[62] Broom, 36.
[63] Broom, 276.
[64] Broom, 461. The original occurrence of the phrase is found on p. 101.
[65] Broom, 461.
[66] Broom, 285.
[67] Broom, 286.
[68] Broom, 286.
[69] Broom, 287.
[70] Broom, 287.
[71] Broom, 119.
[72] Broom, 409-410.
[73] Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, 5.6.
[74] Tractatus, 5.63.
[75] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 32.
[76] McCaffery, ‘Interview,’ 26.