an international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume 2, February 2005, ISSN 1552-5112
Your study is located at
the crossroads of magic and positivism.
That spot is bewitched. Only
theory can break the spell.[1]
Film theory as we know it today did not come into
existence until the late 1960’s, and since then has been dominated by
psychoanalytic ideas. This article seeks
to specifically investigate the influence of Lacanian psychoanalysis on film
theory. Its development will be traced
in two articles through classic film theory, the role of Karl Marx and Louis
Althusser, the contributions of semiotics, the debates surrounding apparatus
theory and the gaze, and finally the input of feminism. While this type of broad overview has been
attempted in many general introductions to film theory, it is hoped here to
provide a rough sketch of its formative stages of development, while filling in
the detail on a number of significant issues that highlight Lacan’s
influence.
It was not until after the First World War that it
became possible to identify two particular groups within film criticism. Spearheading the first of these groups was
the figure of Sergei Eisenstein, whose film-making and theoretical essays
in the 1920’s established a conception of the role of the cinema as a primarily
aesthetic one. According to Eisenstein,
a film’s aesthetic value depended on its ability to transform reality and in
his films this usually took the form of montage.[2] In opposition to Eisenstein were the
impressionists and surrealists. They
also believed the main function of the cinema to be aesthetic, but thought that
the camera itself was enough to render ordinary objects sublime. Their emphasis on cinema as a visual medium
meant that they regarded narrative in many cases as an obstacle that had to be
overcome. This, coupled with their
emphasis on fragmentation, meant that the impressionist / surrealist tradition
was unsuited to the rapidly expanding business of commercial cinema.
Eisenstein and his followers gradually overshadowed
other theoretical groups to the extent that it was not until after the Second
World War, in the 50’s, that any radical development within film theory took
place. This development was primarily
due to the influence of André Bazin and his two essays, ‘The Evolution of the
Language of Cinema’ and ‘The Virtues and Limitations of Montage’, which
critiqued the two most prestigious schools of thought in film at the time:
Eisenstein’s Soviet school of montage and German expressionism (Ray 2001,
7). Bazin overturned existing
conceptions of film by claiming that cinema’s true purpose was the objective
representation of reality. The
expressionists, surrealists and the Soviet school all evinced a belief in the manipulation of reality: Eisenstein
through abstract montage and mise-en-scene,
and the impressionists and surrealists through their elevation of the image
and disregard for other aspects of cinematography. Bazin argued that cinema offered the chance
of completely objective representation for the first time in history. His position has come under severe criticism
from post-structuralists, for whom reality is always a subjective experience.[3] However, it is interesting to note that
contemporary television would seem to have come full circle in a return to
Bazin’s conception of film: reality TV is the ultimate symptom of a desire for
totally objective, unmediated presentation of everyday life.
The influence of Bazin’s theories was short-lived
and the political upheaval that occurred in France in 1968 was the catalyst for
a complete change of direction in film studies.
Bazin’s style of criticism based around the notion of the auteur and the aesthetic function of
cinema soon became outdated as film studies became indisputably political:
‘[t]here was no place outside or above politics; all texts, whatever their
claims to neutrality, had their ideological slant’ (Lapsley and Westlake 1988,
1). Film makers and film critics alike
were forced to consider the relationship between ideology and power and the
position of cinema within that dualism.
This new politically-centered, theoretically-driven film criticism was
given a forum in two highly influential French journals, Cahiers du Cinéma and Cinéthique,
along with their British counterpart Screen. The editorial by Jean-Louis Comolli and
Jean Narboni in the October 1969 issue of Cahiers
illustrates the radical new direction that film studies had taken. In a marked reaction against the subjective,
speculative analyses of classical film theory, Comolli and Narboni stress the
scientific basis of their critique.[4] In addition to scientific methodology, they
also emphasise the political nature of their aims which are heavily influenced
by Marxism. They see film as a product
that becomes transformed into a commodity which ‘is also an ideological product
of the system, which in France means capitalism’ (Comolli and Narboni 1969,
45). Acknowledging their own
imprisonment within capitalist ideology, post-revolution film studies envisaged
that theory would provide the key to unlock their chains. It was through theory that operations of
ideological control in cinema could be recognised, and through theory that
resistance could be asserted. The
post-revolution critics saw the lack of theory in classical film studies as one
of the primary reasons for its impotence:
the
classic theory of cinema that the camera is an impartial instrument which
grasps, or rather is impregnated by, the world in its ‘concrete reality’ is an
eminently reactionary one. What the
camera in fact registers is the vague, unformulated, untheorized, unthought-out
world of the dominant ideology. Cinema is one of the languages through which
the world communicates itself to itself.
They constitute its ideology for they reproduce the world as it is
experienced when filtered through its ideology’. (Conolli and Narboni 1969, 46)
It was the philosophy of Louis Althusser that
provided the political conceptual system for post-revolution film theory. One of the driving forces behind Althusser’s
break with traditional Marxism around 1945 was the desire to establish a
scientific status for his theory in order to bestow upon it a degree of
autonomy. This move was to have a direct
impact on film studies as the first paragraph of Comolli and Narboni’s editorial
elucidates:
Scientific criticism has an obligation to define its fields and
methods. This implies awareness of its
own historical and social situation, a rigorous analysis of the proposed field
of study, the conditions which make the work necessary and those which make it
possible, and the special function it intends to fill. It is essential that we at Cahiers du Cinema should now undertake
just such a global analysis of our positions and aims. (Comolli and Narboni 1969, 43)
It was perhaps this desire for scientific fortification
that attracted Althusser to the theories of Lacan. While psychoanalysis had an enormous direct
influence on film studies, it also influenced it indirectly through the Marxist
theory of Althusser. In order to
re-conceptualise the simplistic base/superstructure model of society espoused
by Marx, Althusser borrowed the psychoanalytic term ‘overdetermination’ in
order to articulate the complex web of conflicting elements, which combine to
generate a historical movement in society.
In psychoanalysis, this term is used to describe how a mental phenomenon
like a symptom can be traced back to several conflicting and often incompatible
desires. J. Laplanche and J. B.
Pontalais define it as ‘[t]he fact that formations of the unconscious
(symptoms, dreams, etc.) can be attributed to a plurality of determining
factors…[t]he formation is related to a multiplicity of unconscious elements
which may be organized in different meaningful sequences, each having its own
specific coherence at a particular level of interpretation’ (Laplanche and
Pontalais 1988, 292).
Althusser’s concept of structural causality is also
redolent of Lacanian psychoanalysis. The
term refers to the way in which ‘[m]en are no longer agents actively shaping
history, either as individuals or classes, but rather are supports of the
process within the structure’ (Lapsley and Westlake 1988, 6). Lacan also emphasizes the primacy of societal
codes (in the form of the symbolic order) in the shaping of subjectivity. The way in which the subject is inculcated
into the social order is described by Althusser as interpellation: a process
explicated in all its complexity by Lacan in the Oedipus and castration
complexes, the mirror stage and the acquisition of language. According to Althusser, interpellation takes
place through ideological state apparatuses (ISA’s): family, religion,
education, media, etc. In Lacanian
terms, these social and familial structures are saturated with symbolic law. Although both Cahiers du Cinema and Cinéthique
used the philosophy of Althusser as the basis for their critique of
ideology, they did so in different ways. For Cinéthique all films were hopeless victims of the ideology of the
ruling class and had to be rejected in their entirety, whereas Cahiers du Cinema divided film into
seven different categories, only one of which it wholly condemned, although
this was the largest category: ‘films which are imbued through and through with
the dominant ideology in pure and unadulterated form, and give no indication
that their makers were even aware of the fact’ (Comolli and Narboni 1969,
46). This emphasis on the ideological
nature of films and of signification in general owes an obvious debt to the
philosophy of Lacan. But although there
are several points of connection between the two theorists, the Althusserian
and Lacanian subject are nonetheless two distinct and often opposing
entities. For Althusser, interpellation
fixes the subject into a position of permanent blindness to the ideological
mechanisms of his/her society. The
Lacanian subject is ceaselessly developing and changing through language, and
although constituted by the symbolic order is ‘the producer as well as the
product of meaning’ (Lapsley and Westlake 1988, 53). This idea is explored more fully in the
following section in relation to the graph of desire.
Robert Lapsley and Micheal Westlake isolate two
aspects of Lacanian theory, which were to prove crucial to film studies. The first is Lacan’s reversal of the
Cartesian notion of subjectivity. Rather
than the subject creating and naming the world, Lacan states that is in fact
language itself, which creates the world, ‘the concept…engenders the thing’
(Lacan 1989, 72). This idea has many
implications for filmic criticism, as speech can thus be conceived of as
already saturated with the predominant ideology, making it difficult or even
impossible to utilise speech to criticize ideological norms. In fact, Lacan even goes so far as to say
that language can never fully
articulate what the subject wishes to say: the unsignifiable order of the real
is evidence of this.
The second of Lacan’s theories that proved
indispensable for film studies is his re-reading of Ferdinand de Saussure. Lacan reverses Saussure’s formula for the
sign, placing language above reality (S/s).
He states that, ‘[f]or the human being the word or the concept is
nothing other than the word in its materiality.
It is the thing itself. It is not
just a shadow, a breath, a virtual illusion of the thing, it is the thing itself’ (Lacan 1987, 178, my italics). Language murders the thing and takes its
place. In this model of the sign, there
is an endless sliding of signifiers over signifieds, which is temporarily
halted by the point de caption. The graph of desire (Lacan 1989, 335)
articulates succinctly the complexities inherent in signification. The horizontal vector represents the
signifying chain, and intersects with the vector ΔS at two
points. The first point of intersection
denotes the constitution of the signifier from ‘a synchronic and enumerable
collection of elements in which each is sustained only by the principle of its
opposition to each of the others’ (Lacan 1989, 336). In short, this point represents the signifier,
which attains its status through its difference from other terms in the system
of language. The second point of
intersection denotes the moment of punctuation, in which the signifier at the
first point of intersection attains its full meaning retroactively. The two points of intersection are not
symmetrical, nor are they intended to be.
The first is ‘a locus (a place rather than a space) and the second is ‘a
moment (a rhythm rather than a duration) (Lacan 1989, 336). The elementary cell of the graph cited here
is simplistic, but serves to illustrate the relationship between subject and
meaning.[5]
Meaning is
produced après-coup by the subject
through the retroactive nature of punctuation (the second point of
intersection) in the subject’s enunciation.
However, the subject is also produced by signification, as the meaning
of the signifier at the first point of signification is a differential meaning,
not an inherent meaning. This means that
the subject must choose from a selection of signifiers that are available to
him/her, which themselves shape and define the signified. Collectively, these signifieds construct the
world in which the subject exists, and so construct subjectivity itself. For Lacan, there is an unending flux between
the subject and signification, and this idea occurs in film studies in several
different ways.
Christian Metz defends the analysis of cinema from a
linguistic or semiotic point of view because although it is not a langue in the Saussurian sense of the
word, it is certainly a language. Metz
argues that the cinema does not constitute a langue for three reasons: because there is no intercommunication;
because it is duplication of reality rather than the unmotivated, arbitrary
relationship between signifier and signified and finally because it lacks ‘the
double articulation that…is the hallmark of natural language’ (Lapsley and
Westlake 1988, 39). Natural language can
be described as having a double articulation because it is comprised of both
words (morphemes) and smaller units, phonemes, which signify nothing in
themselves, but when combined produce morphemes. While the camera shot could in theory be
likened to the phoneme, there are numerous difficulties with this
equation. There are an infinite number
of shots to select from, but there are a finite number of words. Moreover, the meaning of the shot is not
defined by its paradigmatic dimension, i.e. by the other shots which could have
been selected, whereas the meaning of words is
defined paradigmatically. Because of
these difficulties in analyzing cinema through its paradigmatic relationships,
Metz instead embarked upon an analysis of the syntagmatic relationships in
cinema: his ‘grande syntagmatique’
(Lapsley and Westlake 1988, 40).
Metz divides the narrative syntax of the cinema into
eight parts, ranging from the smallest segment, the autonomous shot to the
largest segment, the sequence. While
Metz’s analysis set up a detailed schema for understanding a film’s
construction, it was nonetheless open to criticism. Segments from films could not be categorized
as neatly as Metz imagined and he was also criticized for being so formulaic
that there was little room for practical interpretation of the workings of
meaning and ideology within cinema.
Metz’s grande syntagmatique did
elicit several progressive critical responses however. Film director Pier Paolo Pasolini argued
against Metz’s proposition that there was nothing in the cinema to correspond
to phonemes, which would align it to language’s dual articulation. Pasolini names the smaller units of cinema
‘cinemes’, which represent reality, or objects from reality. Through a process of selection and
combination cinemes were formed into shots, analogous to language’s
morphemes. Umberto Eco criticized
Pasolini’s naivety in supposing that the cinema could articulate an unmediated
reality. Rather, Eco argues that reality
is represented in the cinema through a system of cultural codes which are
intimately connected to ideology. He
states also that cinemes could not be equivalent to phonemes, since phonemes
only possess meaning in combination, whereas cinemes possess meaning in
isolation. Against Metz’s
uni-articulation and Pasolini’s double-articulation, Eco contends that the
cinema has a triple articulation made up of semes, smaller iconic signs which
only attain meaning in relation to semes, and finally the ‘conditions of
perception’ (Lapsley and Westlake 1988, 45), which takes into account the
audience’s perception of light, shade, textures, colours, etc. which contribute
to their understanding of the filmic text.
Later on, Eco revised this model slightly, suggesting that signs are
better thought of as ‘sign-functions correlating a unit of expression with a
unit of content in a temporary
encoding’ (Lapsley and Westlake 1988, 46, my italics), recognizing that signs
are defined by their context and that their meaning cannot be fixed.[6]
The
relationship between the subject and the narrative text in the cinema was
explored by many film critics and much of the remaining sections are concerned
with an analysis of this relationship from various critical viewpoints. One such critic is Colin McCabe, who was on
the editorial board for the revolutionary British film journal Screen in the 1970’s and was also a
regular contributor. Screen took on board the challenge of
analyzing the relationship between ideology, subjectivity and signification,
and did so through psychoanalysis, semiotics and Althusserian Marxism. It is in the structuralist mode that McCabe
theorizes the production of meaning in film in the article that will be
discussed here.[7]
The model for McCabe’s analysis of film is a
literary one. Since the dominant mode of
film was (and still is) realism, McCabe finds his model in the classic realist
text, the nineteenth century novel, which he defines as ‘one in which there is
a hierarchy amongst the discourses which compose the text and this hierarchy is
defined in terms of an empirical notion of truth’ (McCabe 1974, 54). The Marxist influence of McCabe’s analysis is
obvious. Extrapolating the hierarchical
divisions within the realist novel allows him to uncover the mechanisms of
ideology within the text. McCabe divides
the realist novel into narrative prose and object language. Narrative prose is characterised by the
omniscient narrator, informing, commenting and providing judgement on the
object language, the language of the characters, represented in inverted
commas. McCabe states that the narrative
prose is the first order of hierarchy in the novel. It ‘functions as a metalanguage that can state
all the truths in the object language’ (McCabe 1974, 54). The narrative prose attempts to conceal its
status as metalanguage: since its words are not spoken, it is almost as if they
are not there. Its invisibility hides
its function as purveyor of the dominant ideology. In film, McCabe believes that the camera is
analogous to the metalanguage of the classic realist novel: ‘[t]he camera shows
us what happens – it tells the truth against which we can measure the discourses’
(McCabe 1974, 56).
McCabe defines two aspects of the classic realist
text in both novel and film. He states
that ‘[t]he classic realist text cannot deal with the real as
contradictory. In a reciprocal movement
the classic realist text ensures the position of the subject in a relation of
dominant specularity’ (McCabe 1974, 58).
The ‘real’ here does not signify the Lacanian real. It refers rather to the real events which are
related in the subjective discourse of the cinema and conversely in the object
language or dialogue of the realist novel.
He is stating therefore that realist narrative cannot accommodate a
tension between metalanguage and object discourse. The nature of the genre means that the object
discourse must subscribe to the commentary of the metalanguage, and therefore
to the status of metalanguage as ideologically motivated. However, while tension is impossible between
these two hierarchical levels within the film or the novel, it is possible for either to resist the
dominant ideology of society. So while
the two elements are necessarily harmonious within the narrative of filmic
text, in unison they are capable of critique:
the classic realist text (a
heavily ‘closed’ discourse) cannot deal with the real in its contradictions…it
fixes the subject in a point of view from which everything becomes
obvious. There is, however, a level of
contradiction into which the classic realist text can enter. This is the contradiction between the
dominant discourse of the text and the dominant ideological discourses of the
time. (McCabe 1974, 62)
While McCabe’s analysis provides a useful account of
the ‘invisible’ operations of the camera as commentator and interpreter of the
action, it fails to provide a theoretical analysis of how the spectator receives this ideological cinematic code and the
exact nature of the relationship between spectator and film. This task required an analysis of the
subject’s relationship with other subjects, images, language and culture, and
film critics found a theoretical paradigm that explicated all of these factors
in psychoanalysis. The emphasis on the
occasion of consumption (the dialectic between subject and film in the cinema,
when he/she is engaged in the act of perception) is one of the most important
differentiating factors between film theory and literary criticism. This is the central focus of the branch of
film studies known as apparatus theory, which relies most heavily on philosophy
of Lacan.
Metz’s foundational essay ‘The Imaginary Signifier’
is an exemplary account of the film/spectator relationship, providing what was
to become a model for the use of psychoanalytic theory in film criticism. In the scientific manner that characterized
post-revolution film studies, Metz sets out to define exactly what the cinema
is and how it differs from the other arts.
He proposes that the main distinguishing factor is that the cinema is a
signifier whose presence is absence, i.e. the act of perception takes place in
real time, but the spectator is viewing an object which is pre-recorded and
thus already absent: it is the object’s ‘replica
in a new kind of mirror’ (Metz 2000, 410).
He states that, ‘[m]ore than the other arts…the cinema involves us in
the imaginary: it drums up all perception, but to switch it immediately over
into its own absence, which is none the less the only signifier present’ (Metz
2000, 410). Metz’s definition of the
cinema is an accurate one, although he over-emphasises the difference between
film and other arts. All of the arts
involve an element of presence in absence: reading a book or listening to a
piece of music are activities where the action is not directly present. Even the act of watching a play where the
actors are present on stage necessarily involves the agreed absence of reality
(suspension of disbelief), which is a fundamental convention of drama.
Watching
a film necessarily involves for Metz an instance of identification, since
without identification meaning cannot be generated for the subject. The spectator ‘continues to depend in the
cinema on that permanent play of identification without which there would be no
social life’ (Metz 2000, 411). The
question of what exactly the spectator identifies with proves to be more difficult.
The obvious answer is a character in the film, but Metz points out that
not all films contain characters. Even
in instances where characters are present, there cannot be total
identification: the screen is a mirror but not in a literal sense. Metz concludes that the spectator must
identify with the cinematic apparatus itself, and its re-creation of the act of
looking: ‘the spectator identifies with
himself, with himself as pure act of perception…as condition of possibility
of the perceived and hence as a kind of transcendental subject, anterior to
every there is’ (Metz 2000,
413).
Identification is with the projector, the camera and
the screen of the cinematic apparatus.
The projector duplicates the act of perception by originating from the
back of the subject’s head and presenting a visual image in front of the
subject. The various shots of the camera
are akin to the movement of the head. As
vision is both projective and introjective, the subject projects his/her gaze
and simultaneously introjects the information received from the gaze. The cinema replicates this experience, with
the screen functioning as the recording surface for what has been
introjected. Opening the eyes to view
the film, ‘I am the projector, receiving it, I am the screen; in both these
figures together, I am the camera, pointed yet recording’ (Metz 2000, 415).
Identification takes place in the imaginary order. The imaginary is governed by the symbolic,
and the cinema is no exception to this rule.
Any theorization of the imaginary in cinema must pre-suppose the
symbolic since the cinema is a system of signifiers which signify an absent
signified. Metz does not explicitly
acknowledge that the cinematic experience replicates the experience of the
child in the mirror: if the screen takes the place of the childhood mirror,
then both can be said to create a version of reality that is based upon an
illusion. However, Metz does identify
the cinema as characteristically imaginary, since what is depicted is already a
reflection of reality. He focuses on the
imaginary at the expense of the symbolic and this issue has been taken up by
several feminist critics who will be discussed in part two of this
article. This emphasis on the imaginary
generated a large amount of theoretical analysis. Like the childhood mirror, the imaginary
completeness that the screen represents merely serves to disguise an inherent
lack. The means by which this imaginary
completeness is created is known as suture.
Stephen
Heath’s ground-breaking work, Narrative
Space, provides an informed description of suture, foregrounded by a
detailed discussion of filmic narrative space in general. Pivotal to Heath’s analysis is the notion of
‘central projection’ and he outlines the development of this idea from
fifteenth century Italian painting to early photography. It is defined as ‘the art of depicting
three-dimensional objects upon a plane surface in such a manner that the
picture may affect the eye of an
observer in the same way as the natural objects themselves’ (Heath 1993,
69). Central projection, which we now
regard as ‘natural’, dominates modern cinema.
For the illusion of central projection to be fully accurate, it is
essential for the eye of the spectator to be positioned in the central point of
perspective. Anamorphosis is the term
that is used to describe what happens when a painter or a film maker plays with
central projection. This is the
distorted sensation experienced when an image draws the eye to one side. Heath cites Holbein’s ‘The Ambassadors’ as an
example of anamorphosis: ‘playing between ‘appearance’ and ‘reality’, it
situates the centre of the projection of the painting…obliquely to the side,
the sense of the painting…only falling into place (exactly) once the position
has been found’ (Heath 1993, 69).
Although unacknowledged by Heath, the emphasis on the importance of
subject position in maintaining the illusion of reality contains strong echoes
of Lacan’s optical experiment, in which the position of the subject is crucial
in order to maintain the delicate balance between the three orders[8]. Watching a film is also based on an optical
illusion in which images on a flat screen appear three-dimensional and
realistic. The identifications
engendered by film narrative centered around the imaginary order are similarly
based upon méconnaisance.
Heath divides filmic space into space in frame and space out of
frame. The space in frame is ‘narrative
space’. ‘It is narrative significance
that at any moment sets the space of the frame to be followed and ‘read’’
(Heath 1993, 69). This narrative space
is characterized and delimited by various conventions. For example, most films contain a master-shot
in the opening sequence: a shot that shows the whole setting in order to allow
the spectator to integrate themselves into the spatial layout of the film. The conventions of the 180 and 30-degree
rules also regulate the narrative space of the cinema. The 180 degree rule means that the camera
rarely goes beyond the 180 degree line of the screen, in front of which the
spectator would be placed within the narrative space of the film. In order to avoid a jump in narrative space,
which would interrupt the illusion of total visual access to the narrative
space of the film, the 30-degree rule is common practice, which means that the
camera should not attempt a sudden jump of more than 30 degrees. All of these conventions function to maintain
the illusion of reality that the cinema creates. The illusion or misrecognition that is inherent
in the cinematic experience centers around the complex issue of suture.
The
term originates with Lacan, who uses it only once in his seminar of 1965, and
was later transformed into a concept by Jacques-Alain Miller in his article for
Les Cahiers pour l’analyse, later
printed in Screen as ‘Suture (Elements of the Logic of the Signifer)’. In this article, Miller theorizes the notion
of suture as the relationship between the subject and the signifying
chain. Roudinesco illuminates the
objections that Lacan had to this article, which are quite significant in light
of later usages of the term. Unhappy
with Miller’s article, he alludes to it in ‘Science and Truth’, taking a
completely opposing position. Rather
than seeing suture as the closure of the relationship between the subject and
the chain, Lacan favours its openness, and argues that ‘science fails to suture
or produce a complete formalization of the subject’ (Roudinesco 1997,
327). Summarising the polarity and
subsequent impact of the opposing positions of Miller and Lacan, Roudinesco
states that,
although
Miller’s contribution was useful to Lacan, its tenor was quite opposite to his
own. Lacan’s logic of the subject was
based on opening, ambiguity, ambivalence, and the idea of an impossible
mastery; Miller’s interpretation of that logic was the harbinger of all the
dogmas that were to come. (Roudinesco 1997, 327)
In the 1960’s, Jean Pierre Oudart contributed a
description of the operations of suture in cinema to Cahiers. He argues that the
cinema screen initially produces jouissance
in the subject, who is absorbed in the imaginary misrecognition of images,
similar to the experience of the mirror stage.
As always however, the symbolic encroaches upon the imaginary when the
spectator becomes aware of the frame.
This awareness consequently produces an anxiety in the subject who is
unsure whose point of view is being depicted, threatening to shatter the
cinematic illusion. This threat is
forestalled by the traditional shot/reverse shot mechanism, whereby a second
shot allows the first to be shown as a character’s field of vision. This maintains the illusion of completeness
and allows the spectator to remain in his/her position as voyeur. Suture became an important concept in film
studies in both Britain and France until it underwent another transformation
with the advent of deconstruction, where it became ‘a vague notion rather than
a concept, as synonymous with ‘closure’: ‘suture’ signaled that the gap, the
opening, of a structure was obliterated, enabling the structure to
(mis)perceive itself as a self-enclosed totality of representation’ (Zizek
2001, 31). Heath’s narrative space is
thus dependent upon the action of suture since the cinema, as much as the
childhood mirror, poses for the spectator ‘an absence, a lack, which is ceaselessly
recaptured for…the film, the process binding the spectator as subject in the
realization of the film’s space’ (Heath 1993, 88).
From its very beginning
then, throughout its influence by Marxism and semiotics, film theory has relied
on psychoanalytic theory to provide a philosophical, pseudo-scientific and
sociological basis for the conceptualization of the spectator. However, the psychoanalytic subject espoused
by film studies is not without its critics.
Many have accused the discipline of diluting Lacanian theory to serve
their own purposes, reducing the complexities of the Lacanian subject to a
deceiving simplicity. In the second part
of this article, the writings of Joan Copjec and Slavoj Zizek on the issue of
the gaze will be analysed. These
critics, along with other discussed in part two, show that far from the
cinematic screen being a mirror akin to the mirror of childhood described in
Lacan’s mirror stage, that the mirror is in fact a screen, and that the
spectator is not the one who looks, but rather is being looked at.
Bibliography
Adorno, Theodor, 1980. ‘Letter to Walter Benjamin’
in Aesthetics and Politics. ed. by
Frederic Jameson. London: Verso.
Comolli, Jean-Louis and Jean
Narboni, [1969]. ‘Cinema/Ideology
Criticism (1)’ in Contemporary Film
Theory, ed. Anthony Easthope. New York: Longman, 1993. [pp. 43-51]
Heath, Stephen, 1993, ‘From Narrative Space’ in Contemporary
Film Theory. ed. by Anthony Easthope. New York: Longman. [pp. 68-94]
Lacan, Jacques, 1989. Ecrits: a
Selection. Translated by Alan
Sheridan. London: Routledge.
Lacan, Jacques, (1953-4), Le Séminaire. Livre 1. Les écrits techniques
de Freud, 1953-4, ed. Jacques Alain Miller, Paris: Seuil, 1975 [The Seminar, Book 1, Freud’s Papers on
Technique, 1953-4, trans John Forrester, with notes by John Forrester, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1987].
McCabe, Colin, [1974], ‘From Realism and the Cinema: Notes on Some Brechtian Theses’ in Contemporary Film Theory, edited by
Anthony Easthope. New York: Longman, 1993. [pp. 53-67]
Metz, Christian, 2000. ‘The Imaginary Signifier’ in Film and Theory: An Anthology, ed. by
Robert Stam and Toby Miller. Oxford: Blackwell. [pp. 403-435]
Ray, Robert B., 2001. How Film Theory Got Lost and Other Mysteries in Cultural Studies. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Lapsley, Robert and Michael Westlake, 1988. Film Theory: An Introduction. Manchester:
Manchester University Press.
Roudinesco, Elisabeth, (1994), Jacques Lacan: Esquisse d’une vie, histoire d’un système de pensée. Librairie Arthème
Fayard. [Jacques Lacan. Trans. Barbara Gray. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1997].
Zizek, Slavoj, 2001. The Fright of Real Tears: Krystof Kieślowski between Theory and
Post Theory. London: BFI Publishing.
[1] ‘Letter to Walter
Benjamin’ in Aesthetics and Politics, edited
by Frederic Jameson, p. 129.
[2] Eisenstein’s
stance on this issue was foregrounded by the earlier pictorialism movement,
which sought to disguise the photographic image by disguising it as art (Ray
2001, 3).
[3] Ray states that
Bazin’s philosophy is an example of what Derrida names ‘unmediated presence’
(Ray 2001, 8).
[4] While the
aesthetic bias of Eisenstein’s criticism was rejected, his theoretical writings
were admired. Along with his Russian
contemporaries, he was perceived as contributing to the theoretical matrix of
film studies (Comolli and Narboni 1969, 50).
[5] Lacan develops this graph in four stages in
‘The Subversion of the Subject and the Dialectic of Desire in the Freudian
Unconscious’ (Lacan 1989, 323-360).
[6] This view also
bears the influence of post-structuralists like Lacan and Derrida who insist
upon the temporality of meaning in signification. For Derrida, ‘il n’ya pas hors de contexte’: there is nothing outside the
context.
[7] Colin McCabe’s
analyses are not confined to structuralism.
On the contrary, he is a well-regarded film critic who is capable of
analyzing in many different modes. This
particular article has been chosen as an example of structuralist criticism.
[8] See seminar 1.
an international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume 2, February 2005, ISSN 1552-5112