an international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume 13, Winter 2016/2017, ISSN 1552-5112
Notes
Towards a Distinction: On Postmodernism and Poststructuralism
It
is almost a truism to say that postmodernism is
indefinable. Whilst not necessarily true it certainly has a large
degree of
terminological plasticity, and frequently finds itself conflated
with other
terms (in this case poststructuralism). Whilst this is
understandable, it is
perhaps a mistake, so what I want to do is suggest a few lines of
flight and
points of comparison that might provide grounds for distinguishing
the two
terms. This isn’t intended to function as the sole way of
understanding this
topic, and I will (for the sake of brevity more than anything)
skip over
thinkers that some would consider being essential. As I said, I’m
just trying
to give one way of understanding these two ideas.
“Postmodern”
as a term was not ‘coined by’
Jean-François Lyotard in The
Postmodern
Condition (1979), but it was certainly the point at which it
entered a
broadly philosophical usage. Before Lyotard, it was generally used
in art
criticism, literary criticism and in relation to aesthetics,
appearing
sporadically throughout the early twentieth century in a variety
of contexts.
Then comes Lyotard’s (in)famous book and the quote which has
appeared in
countless undergraduate essays, that postmodernism is ‘incredulity
toward
meta-narrative.’ (What these quotes cut out is the first part of
the sentence –
which in full reads “Simplifying to the extreme; I define
postmodern as
incredulity towards meta-narratives.”)
However,
before turning to Lyotard’s arguments, it is
worth situating philosophical postmodernism as something that is
both
historically contingent and which has clear philosophical
forerunners for which
there are (at least) three figures who must be considered as
essential – Marx,
Kierkegaard and Nietzsche. The common understanding of
postmodernism (detailed
below) is that of something which has roots in the work of these
three
thinkers. For example, the notion of a kind of de-realized society
is one
Kierkegaard was familiar with, as in his Two
Ages:
A Literary Review (1846) he described modern society as a
network of
relations in which individuals are leveled into a kind of abstract
phantom
known as “the public.” This public, in contrast to the older forms
of
community, “never are and never can be united in an actual
situation or
organization.” Marx wrote extensively on the spectral, ghostly and
abstracted
qualities of capitalism whereby concrete objects lose their
use-value and melt
into the spectral realm of exchange-value. Workers cease to see
themselves in
their labour and become alienated from themselves – a key point in
the
postmodern worldview. In Nietzsche, (see for example Twilight of the Idols (1889)) we find that the “true world” becomes
a superfluous idea or as he elegiacally puts it, ‘the last breath
of a
vaporising reality.’[1] This dissolution between the real and
the apparent
is a key theme to much later postmodernist writing and is
suggested by
Nietzsche’s first book The
Birth of
Tragedy (1872). Furthermore, in his 1874 essay “On the Uses
and
Disadvantage of History for Life” he would go on to argue that the
life of a
culture depended upon the ability to repeat a kind of unhistorical
moment – a
kind of forgetting, that is done alongside continuous historical
development.
For Nietzsche then, we cannot stand outside of history, and cannot
conceive of
the past times as stages on the way to the present. Or, in other
words, ‘all of
this has happened before, and will happen again.’
And
so after that brief postmodern philosophical
history, back to the famous quote… There are many reasons why this
quote is as
popular as it is – it is obvious, it is short, pithy and provides
an immediate
way into what is a rather conceptually dense idea. ‘Scepticism
towards
metanarratives’ allows for us to understand postmodernism as a
kind of
historical period marked by a lack of belief in any organising
totality.
Postmodernism is fragmentation, relativism, and, (if certain
hot-takes from
about 1990 to the present are to be believed) the collapse of all
moral values
into a kind of nihilism and abandonment of the concept of truth.
This does a
colossal disservice to Lyotard’s book, which was originally
published as less a
philosophy book and more a book on pedagogy. The subtitle was A Report on the Conditions of
Knowledge and
the book as a whole, drawing on Wittgenstein and speech act
theory, sought to
examine how the “language games” of science, art and literature
had changed
since the end of the nineteenth century. In short, in an
increasingly
technologized age, knowledge has become information – data that is
encoded and
decoded, transmitted, etc. As a result, what is necessary is a
kind of
pragmatics of communication whereby this information can be
decoded and a kind
of value judgment can be made. Crucially though, those that occupy
the position
of ‘judge’ are themselves caught within these same language games
and thus the
question inevitably becomes one of legitimation. And so, to quote
Lyotard,
“there is a strict interlinkage between the kind of language
called science and
the kind called ethics and politics.” Science is, in the modern
age
inextricably bound up in government and administration, given the
large amounts
of money and grand institutions required. (Any scientist who has
applied for
research funding will tell you this is inarguably true.)
In
addition, Lyotard argues that science and
philosophy have become increasingly disconnected from one another.
Science
sought to distinguish itself from old received forms of knowledge
and
philosophy, through what Lyotard calls the “dialectics of Spirit,
the
hermeneutics of meaning, the emancipation of the rational or
working subject,
or the creation of wealth,” all of which, seek to legitimate
science. Science
however, plays the language game of denotation to the exclusion of
all other
discourses and thus displaces what we could term narrative
knowledge –
particularly meta-discourses like philosophy. In an era of
technological
sophistication, knowledge becomes a means not an end. Science is
thus separated
from philosophy, free to develop its own language game further but
often unable
to form a coherent narrative around issues such as ethics and
morality. As
Lyotard expresses it, lamenting “the ‘loss of meaning’ in
postmodernity boils
down to mourning the fact that knowledge is no longer principally
narrative.”
Instead what we have in the age of postmodernity are independent
language games
– no longer coherent narratives, but rather “clouds” of linguistic
combinations
through which the individual moves.
We
move from position to position within each
language game, skipping from sender, to addressee, to referent and
so on. This
too has its own impact on subjectivity – the individual as a
coherent, singular
“I” becomes a multitude, a heterogeneous combination of diverse
subject-positions. (The anti-humanism of postmodernity is an
essential part of
the broader philosophical project but is one that for reasons of
space, I
shan’t go into here.) Lyotard would also be heavily influential to
Baudrillard’s work on hyperreality. Baudrillard argued that the
commodity is
not simply an object with use-value for exchange but a
commodity-sign. Culture
as a whole is constituted through the flow of these images. As he
put it in Simulacra and
Simulation (1981), “we
live everywhere in an aesthetic hallucination of reality.” Here
then, we see
both the reorganisation of society, along with the rethinking and
reconstitution
of traditional, or perhaps more accurately, Enlightenment notions
of the
individual.
The
other grand text of philosophical postmodernism
is Fredric Jameson’s Postmodernism,
Or
the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism (1991) which, whilst
agreeing with
Baudrillard in part, differed on the ground of cause. Jameson
defines
postmodernity as a reorientation of the subject’s relationship to
the spatial
and temporal (Jameson readings of postmodern architecture make
this point
particularly well.) Fundamentally, Jameson argues that we are
unable to “place”
ourselves - and culture reflects this spatial and temporal
dislocation. We are
historically, culturally and even geographically, displaced by the
engine of
global, networked late capitalism. As a result, culture is marked
by a
cannibalisation of older styles, as well as dominated by forms of
pastiche, and
a nostalgia for history, in which history is not an object of
representation
but of stylistic connotation. This shift is, for Jameson,
something which
possesses a historical reality - expressive of the nature of our
contemporary
moment existing under late-stage global capitalism. Late-stage
capitalism
extends commodification into every aspect and realm of our social
and personal
lives, transforming the real into the image.
In
short then, postmodernism could be understood as a
particular historical period with concomitant philosophical
practises marked by
a response to modernism. In contrast, poststructuralism is a
particular set of
critical practises which have emerged at a certain historical
moment.
Postmodernity is the precondition of poststructuralism. To put it
as simply as
possible I would say that poststructuralism is a certain set of
strategies for
reading and writing texts or, in other words, poststructuralism is
a set of
theories around the relationship between humans and the practice
of reproducing
meanings.
However,
first, some necessary context – to
understand postmodernism we must look at modernity and so, to
understand
poststructuralism we must examine structuralism. In the most basic
terms
structuralism argues that human culture can be understood by means
of a
structure (most commonly language) that differs from concrete
objects and
abstract ideas - a “third order,” that mediates between the two
(for more on
this see Deleuze’s “How do we recognize structuralism?”) In
literary terms
then, structuralist analysis would aim to relate an individual
text to a wider
structure - genre for example or a universalised narrative model.
Structuralism
can, in a sense, be understood as an attempt to ground cultural,
literary or
philosophical analysis on more coherent “scientific” grounds. A
good example of
this is the work of Vladimir Propp, the Russian formalist who
defined Russian
folktales through a series of narrative functions, each of which
were given a
certain symbol. In short, Propp’s formalist criticism allows for
the folktale
to be represented as an equation (for more and to try this out, go
here: http://www.stonedragonpress.com/vladimir_propp/propp_generator_v1.htm.)
Structuralism
can be seen as a response to phenomenology,
where knowledge is based upon the knower – phenomena as it appears
in the mind
of an individual subject. For the structuralist, phenomenology is
too arbitrary
and insubstantial and thus rather than focus on individuals, a
focus on
language allows for more secure judgements to be made. But as the
great
Catherine Belsey points out, there is “the structuralist danger of
collapsing
all difference.” In the late 1950s and early 1960s there emerged a
disparate
group of academics (many of whom would reject the
poststructuralist label) who
sought to question the attempt to base foundational knowledge on
either
phenomenology or language. In contrast to structuralism, which
sought to
understand knowledge, poststructuralism sought to analyse how
knowledge was produced.
To do so, poststructuralism seeks to question the binary
oppositions and
hierarchies that underpin structuralist ideas – in the work of
many, but most
famously Jacques Derrida, these hierarchical binaries of
presence/absence or
voice/text are “deconstructed” as Derrida shows that the
apparently “dominant”
idea is subservient to the weaker of the pair. The only way in
which meaning
can be understood is to unpick the multiplicity of knowledge
systems which
produce this seemingly fixed singular meaning. Furthermore, one of
the most
compelling poststructuralist criticisms of structuralist thought
is that
underlying structures are conditioned and informed by both culture
and history,
and of course, both of these are open to biases, misunderstandings
and
misinterpretations. To understand an object or a text then, it is
necessary to
examine both the object itself and the various systems of
knowledge which
produce it. To put this in a more practical and less abstract
sense, there is
an important tension that poststructuralist theories explore and
discern:
firstly, consciousness is not simply the origin point of the
language we speak,
so much as the product of the meanings and images we learn and
reproduce. At
the same time, communication changes ALL THE TIME and we can
intervene in these
meanings and the norms our culture takes for granted.
In
short then, perhaps the easiest way to understand
this is to say that poststructuralism explores the tensions
between ourselves
and our language. Most of the time our language is (or seems)
almost
transparent. We ‘see through it’ concerned with not what it is,
but what it can
do for us. However, language is essential – it is how we navigate
the world,
it’s how we survive and it’s how we define who and what we are.
Even the basic
things we need, like food and shelter are not things we encounter
outside of
language. One of the basic features of poststructuralism is that
the
differences by which we navigate the world are not ‘givens’ but
produced by the
symbolizing systems we learn and interpret. We learn to
communicate at such a
young age that we assume language is something we see through to
‘real’ things,
but importantly these things are not real but maybe completely
imaginary.
Perhaps we might say that ideas are the source of meaning but in
reality, this
operates the other way around.
In
short, ideas are the effects of the meanings we
learn and (constantly) reproduce. Thus, here we see the challenge
of
poststructuralism to our conception of how we make ourselves
“meaning animals”
Meaning is, as already mentioned, historically situated too –
poststructuralism
often gets tied to postmodernity so it’s worth thinking about ‘the
modern.’
After all, modern history is perhaps the last 300 years; modern
language,
occurs around the last 5-600 years and modern art perhaps within
the last 80
years or so. The poststructuralist challenge to modern ideas is
itself a
product of the last few decades. A very ‘modern’ idea in and of
itself, right?
Arguably then, ‘modern,’ as a term, has no positive content, but
is defined
simply by difference. ‘Modern’ is not ‘ancient’ or ‘medieval’ and
so on. Even
though ‘modern’ seems to have no positive content, we are able to
use it, and
know what we mean when we do. Saussure wrote in his Course in General Linguistics (1916), that “in language there are
only differences without positive terms” and this becomes a key
refrain of
poststructuralist thinking explored in the work of thinkers such
as Judith
Butler, Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Julia Kristeva and many
more. Living
through postmodern neoliberal capitalism we must renegotiate the
relationship
between the subject, the world and language, and it this
renegotiation that
poststructuralism seeks to undertake. We often change how we think
of ourselves,
for as Catherine Belsey puts it in Postructuralism
(2002), poststructuralism reveals that “we are…creatures of
difference.”
an international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume
13, Winter 2016/2017, ISSN
1552-5112
Notes
[1] Editor’s note: Arguably, Jean Baudrillard would refer to the very same Nietzschean last breath, but as ‘paroxysm’ roughly one hundred years later. See the English translation Paroxysm (1998), translated from Le Paroxyste indifférent: Entretiens avec Philippe Petit (1997), for example.