an
international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume 18, Summer 2021, ISSN 1552-5112
Come-Hither for a Deleuzian
Psychology?
Introduction
…while philosophers cannot, and should
not, pretend to do the work of social scientists for them,
they can greatly contribute to the job
of ontological clarification.
—Manuel DeLanda
This paper will discuss how critically-informed psychologists might reinvent
‘mainstream’ Psychology by drawing upon various thinkers whose work centres around “the philosophical tradition of process
thinking” (Brown, 2018, p. 51). One way
to consider the possibility of such a merger (or re-emergence), is to revisit
Deleuze and Guattari’s (1994), What is Philosophy?. In this opus, they describe the subject
matter of Science, Art and Philosophy,
respectively. For them, scientists
handle knowledge, artists are concerned with the creation of affects and
percepts, and philosophers are tasked with the invention of concepts (Deleuze
& Guattari, 1994). However, Brown (2012) rightly notes that the
social sciences are omitted from this triangular schema. As a result, there is no “complementary
‘plane of social science’” (Brown, 2012, p. 107). Despite the validity of this point, here, the
phrase, ‘social science,’ is deployed in a rather one-size-fits all manner –
and thereby neglects any significant differences between and within these
disciplines. Thus, this article seeks to
address with greater specificity how Psychology, rather than social science in
general, might relate to Deleuze and Guattari’s
(1994) triad.
To plug the lacunae opened up by the abovementioned oversights, let us first of
all turn to Manuel DeLanda’s ambitiously titled, ‘A New Philosophy of Society: Assemblage
Theory and Social Complexity’, which describes how various social
scientific theories can be safely rearticulated by his Assemblage Theory
(AT). Mixing philosophy and (natural)
science, DeLanda (2006) argues that for such
co-option to occur, the social scientific theory in question must follow AT’s
golden rule of focusing exclusively upon “relations of exteriority” (p.
10). In this tome, he places a select
number of social scientific theories (note, chiefly taken from sociology)
within his framework. DeLanda (2006) suggests that such a move would
ontologically enlighten the social sciences, thereby improving their questionable
(from his perspective) epistemological foundations. This assertion has led Brown and Stenner
(2009) to observe how DeLanda appears to position
himself as the self-appointed philosopher-in-charge of the social
sciences. However, the purpose of this
article is not to discuss the pros and cons of AT, but to discuss various ways
to redefine Psychology as a specialist subject.
This requires a re-think as to its chosen object of analysis. In fact, this paper fully condones DeLanda’s emphasis upon exteriority, and posits that in
rejecting references to any form of psychic interiority (Freud’s
(2011) “depth-psychology” (p. 18), psychologists could radically re-configure
their subject matter and, in turn, their
practices.
DeLanda’s
(2006) work thereby provides a useful starting point for the discussions
covered herein. Thus, the main focus of this paper is therefore to explore how
Psychology, by determining its own specialist objects of analysis, can
construct its own ‘plane,’ or more plainly: point of view. By entertaining this possibility, this essay
emphatically rejects any attempts to turn Psychology into an inferior form of
either philosophy or (natural) science, on the grounds of its markedly
different subject matter. Nevertheless,
this is not to rule out how psychology, as an independent subject, could be
enriched by drawing upon philosophical and (natural) scientific insights. After all, this would constitute “thought as heterogenesis” (Deleuze & Guattari,
1994, p. 199).
From the outset, then, one must bear in
mind that psychological phenomena are in no way equivalent to that of
philosophy, art or (natural) science. As
Brown (2012) asserts, social scientific objects “are in every sense
‘overdetermined.’ They are complex
admixtures of cultural, political and moral ferment, bereft of any clear
ontological surety, and unmoored form any definite epistemological framework”
(p. 104). As a result, one cannot simply
dismiss “the political nature” (Brown, 2012, p. 104) of Psychology, in order for it to fit snuggly with the scientistic criteria
of other distinct, but sometimes related, subjects. In fact, when it comes to re-designing
Psychology, one observes an impasse between, on the one hand, wanting to
theorise subjectivity and, on the other, trying to remain
‘objective’ at all costs. As Guattari (2000) lucidly puts it, thus: “It is as though a
scientistic superego demands that psychic entities are reified and insists that
they are only understood by means of extrinsic coordinates” (p. 36).
For Deleuze and Guattari (1994) - and by implication only - the subject
matter of Psychology cannot be
‘concepts,’ ‘blocs of sensation’, or ‘functives.’ So, how are Psychology’s
objects of study to be conceived? Brown
(2012) suggests that due to their invariable instability, one could refer to
social scientific objects as “‘implicatives’” (p.
117). Intriguingly, Bateson (1979)
called ideas, as well as their examples, “‘no-things’” (p. 11). But what would constitute the ‘no-things’ of
Psychology? Some apt examples would include; mental distress (Tucker & Goodings,
2014); autism (Brown, 2012); types of attention (Hayles,
2017); obsessive-compulsive disorder (Wise, 2000); and voice-hearing (Blackman,
2010) (to list but a selection). Thus,
in order to contemplate how psychologists might go about generating theories as
to the constitution of these ‘implicatives’ or ‘no-things,’ perhaps they might cherry-pick from other
disciplines, which address the same or similar themes. Indeed, when writing about cinema, Deleuze
(2006) utilized this same approach: “It was not a matter of applying philosophy
to cinema. I just went straight from
philosophy to cinema and back again, from cinema to philosophy” (p. 283). Following this logic, Psychology might
benefit from such to-and-fro collaborations with other specialisms. In fact, such a move, would avoid the
pitfalls of trying to “either integrate or oppose” (Brown, 2012, p. 118) other
disciplines, whilst maintaining Psychology’s singularity in relation to its own
empirical endeavours.
For Nichterlein
(2018), this task demands that critically-minded
psychologists start to think in “a different way to that in which we have been
trained” (p. 8). Hence, the primary
objective of this essay is to consider how paradigms taken from process
philosophies could be used to inform and update psychological theory and practice, and move it away from its
current emphasis on the inward-looking - and backward-looking (remember
psychoanalysis) - Cartesian subject with its neatly split mind and body. Such a perspective is particularly
problematic because it unquestionably (and lazily) assumes that this individual
is a pre-given, thinking ‘entity.’ As
such, Psychology misses the overall process which leads to the formation of
that individual, which is something which Gilbert Simondon
(1992) refers to as “the problem of individuation” (p. 297). Following this criticism, this essay condones
Nichterlein’s (2018) forward-looking suggestion that,
in order to overcome this (continual) error,
Psychology should change its “unit of analysis”, by scrutinising
“the workings of an assemblage” from which “the subject – as a subject –
emerges” (pp. 9-10). Here, ‘assemblage’
roughly refers to the process of arranging a body (affect) in one way of
another (Deleuze & Guattari, 2013). Thus, by looking at relations (bodies, or
affects) and how they might influence one another so as to produce our
(ongoing) experiences (Deleuze & Guattari, 2013),
we might avoid the tacit epistemologically-based
assumption that underlines Psychology’s present-day thinking: that “all matters
are rational decisions made by individual persons in isolation from one
another” (DeLanda, 2006, p. 3).
But before I turn to
the theories of affect which might help alter this unhelpful Cartesian grounding,
it is firstly necessary to offer a brief overview of process philosophy itself,
in order to understand how it could be used to inform
and change contemporary theory and practice within Psychology. Indeed, the theoretical background of
Blackman, Massumi, and Serres’
work can be traced back to the ‘process philosophies’ of William James, Alfred
North Whitehead (especially), Henri Bergson, and Charles Sanders Peirce,
amongst others. Undoubtedly, this particular philosophical tradition has a variegated history;
typically backdated to Heraclitus’ metaphysical assertion that the world is the
product of “volatile flux” (Rescher, 2000, p.
5). Today, the phrase, “process
philosophy,” is often used as “a catchphrase for the doctrines of Alfred North
Whitehead and his followers” (Rescher, 2000, p. 3).
In fact, in Process
and Reality, Whitehead (1978) outlines precisely how his own philosophy
follows Spinoza in replacing morphological “‘substance-quality’” descriptions
with accounts “of dynamic process” (p. 7).
In addition, this metaphysics rejects “subject-predicate forms of
thought,” contending that nothing can be said to exist outside of the
ever-fluctuating, external relations between “actual entities” and “other actual
entities” (Whitehead, 1978, p. 7). Here,
“‘actual entities’” or “actual occasions” are not things, but rather, events
(Whitehead, 1978, p. 18). In sum, all of these aforementioned process philosophers sought to
forge new theories of experience at odds with both “Cartesian dualism and scientific
materialism” (McHenry, 1995, p. 2). It
is for this precise reason, that a processual approach might provide the
ontological framework for new psychological paradigms informed by an altogether
different type of materialism: one that shifts Psychology’s attention away from
its current emphasis upon thinking subjects, and toward bodies and minds which
are produced in and through our ongoing experiences.
Immaterial Bodies That Matter
The act of being wise is the art of
knowing what to overlook.
—William James
To address this task, I would like to
begin by discussing Lisa Blackman’s (2012) book, Immaterial Bodies: Affect, Embodiment, Mediation. Here, Blackman (2012) proposes that, rather
than removing ‘the subject’ from the picture, we could employ a genealogical
approach so as to reconceptualize subjectivities (or
experiences) as both multiple and open. This promising standpoint, posits that “nineteenth century
models of personhood” offer “a more subliminal subject,” one that is “not assumed to be informationally closed to the environment”
(Blackman, 2012, p. 23). In support,
Blackman (2012) draws upon insights from the ‘Subliminal Psychology’ movement
of the late nineteenth century, which encompasses theories by James, Sidis, and
others. In this view, affective
transmission – how bodies connect with one another - necessarily requires a
mediating open ‘psyche,’ not simply a body with an autonomic nervous
system. (This is Brian Massumi’s (2002) materialist position, which will be
discussed in the next sub-section).
In order to theorise the
psychological mechanisms involved in this abovementioned process, Blackman
(2010) offers the concept of ‘threshold phenomena’, which encompasses hypnotic
suggestion and telepathy, respectively.
In this usage, ‘suggestion’ refers to “a diverse range of actions
registered and transmitted between bodies that cross the divide between the
somatic and the psychological” (Blackman, 2012, p. 52). This (re-)introduction of mimetic phenomena
is utilized so as to invite “leaps, gaps, tensions,
ruptures and conflicts to conceptions of change and transformation” (Blackman,
2012, p. 189). For Blackman (2012), a
newfound emphasis on affectivity within Psychology represents an opportunity to
“develop models of the psychic, psychological and subjectivity which extend our
conceptions of mind, brain, body, and world across space and time” (p. 191).
Consequently, this perspective calls for a much greater consideration of
“‘immateriality’” - that is, “the body’s potential for psychic or psychological
attunement” (Blackman, 2012, p. xxv).
Promisingly, Blackman’s (2012) writing draws Psychology’s attention to
material/immaterial and human/nonhuman bodies.
Indeed, throughout this book the inevitable entanglements of minds and
bodies are highlighted in such a way as to set psychologists the task of theorising exactly how “brain-body-world couplings”
(Blackman, 2012, p. 24) function – as processes – which become attuned over extended periods of time. In turn, empirical attention must
subsequently turn toward “suggestive topologies in ways which challenge the
separation between affect and cognition” (Blackman, 2012, p. 123). Here, the theoretical priority is to avoid,
at all costs, a reduction of mind to
body, in favour of an emphasis on their inevitable
entanglements.
The promise of this
position for the reinvention of Psychology rests upon its call to “attend to
the fact that we can be both one yet many, depending on the different milieux
that produce the possibility of experience” (Blackman, 2012, p. xxiv). Blackman’s (2012) processual approach to
minds and bodies is entirely consistent with all other ecologically-informed
approaches to the mind, whereby this phenomenon is seen as being “everywhere – in the sense that we cannot
extract it from the myriad processes through which it is continuously enacted –
and nowhere in particular, because it
is not a ‘thing’ that has a simple location in some place or other” (Brown,
2018, p. 51). Overall, Blackman’s (2012)
calling to take note of “experiences and practices which challenge the
foundational model of autonomous subjectivity at the heart of the psychological
sciences” (p. 24), puts her thinking in line with other recent attempts to
negotiate a new raison d’être for Psychology (Brown, 2012; Nichterlein & Morss, 2017; Nichterlein, 2018).
Although an emphasis on the
inseparability of affect and cognition is to be condoned, Blackman’s (2012) theorisations regarding subjectivity do retain some form of
“psychological subject” (p. 74). At this
point, I wish to argue that this insistence upon keeping any form of ‘subject’
(implicitly a human one) – albeit in an idealized, historical guise – can, and
should, be rendered a problematic and unnecessary move. There are two main reasons for this
objection. Firstly, it reifies something
which simply does not exist.
As Nietzsche (2006) emphatically stated: “there is no ‘being’ behind the
deed, its effect and what becomes of it; ‘the doer’ is invented as an
afterthought” (p. 26). As such, Blackman’s
(2012) perspective arguably replaces the split Cartesian subject (of
Psychology) with a unified, and yet, idealized version of the same
illusion. Secondly, this subject-based
affective paradigm counters recent attempts by psychologists, such as Brown
(2012), who suggest that we might attend to assemblages (bodies, or
multiplicities) as a means through which Psychology could (finally) usurp “the
royal place of the subject” (p. 106). If
this markedly contrasting position were to be adopted, psychological research
would need to focus upon the ‘becomings’ of nonhuman
and human assemblages (Deleuze & Guattari, 2013)
which relate to its specialist areas of concern (such as those listed
previously). Such a move might give rise
to a non-anthropocentric and immanent psychology; one which displays “an
increased awareness of the material grounding of psychological operations”
(Brown, 2018, p. 55). Such a radically
materialist approach is, however, completely at odds with Blackman’s (2012)
model of affectivity because within that paradigm, ultimately it is the mind,
and not the body, that is the executor.
Individuations without
subjects
Passage precedes
construction.
—Brian Massumi
Insightfully, Blackman (2012) contends
that theorists of affect, particularly so-called Deleuzo-Spinozists
(such as Brian Massumi), are too concerned with
corporeality, and are thereby far too willing to separate bodily affects from
cognitions. Consequently, these
theorists fail to offer any detailed account of the psychological mechanisms
which underlie subjectivity. In fact,
Blackman (2012) suggests that what is problematic about such conceptualisations of affectivity is that, whereas the body
is conceived of as entirely dynamic, the mind is depicted as the passive by-product
of underlying physiological processes.
With this cogent point in mind, let us now turn to Massumi’s
(2002) contrasting onto-relational paradigm in order to
see to what extent Blackman (2012) is correct with this critique of ontological
materialism. In turn, I shall discuss
the ramifications of these criticisms when one is considering the deployment of
such a perspective within Psychology.
Like Blackman (2012),
Brian Massumi’s (2002) theory position draws much of
its inspiration from various process philosophies. Most significantly, much of its inspiration
emanates from materialist thinkers such as Spinoza and Deleuze,
respectively. Indeed, Massumi (2002) stays true to their key tenet by rooting
one’s ontology in bodily affects.
Crucially, this is done without recourse to a pre-existent psychological
subject (contra Blackman (2012)).
Thus, this emergent - or virtual - philosophy could be used to direct
Psychology’s empirical eye - first and foremost - towards bodily forces, but
without actually jettisoning a consideration of
psychological processes. But, unlike
Blackman’s (2012) approach, Massumi (2002) is
insistent that affects and ideas must be treated as corresponding to different
dimensions. Thus, he argues that it is
“only when the idea of the affection is doubled by an idea of the idea of the affection that it attains the level of
conscious reflection” (Massumi, 2002, p. 31). In essence, what Massumi
(2002) postulates is that non-conscious, impersonal affects precede conscious
personalized emotions and thoughts in a virtual, never-ending ontological
feedback loop.
Let us now consider
Blackman’s (2012) previously mentioned criticism, which argues that this
approach disregards psychological processes.
To recap: for Blackman (2012) these Deleuzo-Spinozist
paradigms replace the mind with a “lively nervous system or bodily
materiality that is viewed as dynamic, responsive and autonomous from
intentionality and cognition” (p. 22).
Indeed, this adroit criticism becomes apparent in Massumi’s
(2002) description of cognition as an epiphenomenon: an “autonomic tendency”
(p. 32). And by stressing how a specific
region of the physical body is the continual source of all subsequent relations
with the world, it is easy to see why Blackman (2012) effectively accuses Massumi (2002) of having a propensity for biological
reductionism. However, despite this
objection, Massumi’s (2002) virtual philosophy does
fully account for the production of
psychological phenomena, in that it describes how the body “infolds
contexts, … volitions and
cognitions that are nothing if not situated” (p. 30). In fact, Massumi’s
(2002) Spinozism, conceives of affections as “reverberations” (p. 37).
Evidently, then, there is no omission of either ‘the psyche’ or
intentionality: only the elimination of a ‘subject’ with a mind inside its
body. Indeed, throughout his work Massumi (2002) follows other contemporary theorists, like
John Protevi (2011), in maintaining “that cognition
is fundamentally biological” (p. 29).
This article fully concurs with this position, and
contends that if Psychology were to embrace a radically materialist ontological
framework, in the vein of Massumi’s (2002) approach,
it would have the wherewithal to begin to theorise “subjectless individuations” (Deleuze, 1995, p.
116).
And as Deleuze (1995) insists: “There’s no subject, but a
production of subjectivity: subjectivity has to be produced, when its time
arrives, precisely because there is no subject” (pp. 113-114).
Consequently, any attempts by
psychologists to retain any type of universalist ‘subject’ – of history, of
language, etc, etc. - are to be deemed, not only
uncritical, but also profoundly colonizing: “Transcendence: a specifically
European disease” (Deleuze & Guattari, 2013, p.
19). So, if one wishes that Psychology
studies affects (bodies), ‘the subject’ must be seen for what it is: “a habit,
nothing but a habit in a field of immanence, the habit of saying I”
(Deleuze & Guattari, 1994, p. 48). What does,
nevertheless, (come to) exist is an affective body
which is at “one with its transitions” (Massumi,
2002, p. 15). These ‘transitions’
necessarily include its cognitions, which significantly, must also be seen as
affects, albeit immaterial ones (Deleuze & Guattari,
2013). Taking this logic further,
Blackman’s (2012) insistence upon keeping a (human) subject – albeit in an idealised, historical guise – can be rendered problematic
in Massumi’s (2002) approach, which, I contend does
not mistake ‘the subject’ for the mind.
In essence, what Massumi’s (2002) Deleuzo-Spinozist paradigm does offer Psychology is a means
of retaining its concern with ‘the psyche’ – in spite of
Blackman’s (2012) noted concern. Massumi’s (2002) radically alternative paradigm might
thereby afford Psychology a chance to (finally) recognise
that it is the individual body qua assemblage (Deleuze & Guattari, 2013) which is produced - and not its ‘subject.’
This last point has
important implications for Psychology as both a subject specialism and as an applied
practice. For instance, therapeutic
settings can subsequently be used to help provide the conditions of possibility
for the creation of new subjectivities (experiences) by drawing all parties’
attention to bodies (affects) of all kinds, and their power [puissance]
(Deleuze & Guattari, 2013). Historically, what has made this task
particularly problematic is concepts such as ‘the subject’ and ‘subjectivities’
are often used synonymously by both psychologists and philosophers alike. To help avoid this continual and mistaken
interchangeable usage, one might turn to Guattari’s
(2000) distinction between ‘the individual’ and ‘components of
subjectification.’ This latter concept
is couched in terms of ‘vectors,’ which are akin to nodes which “do not necessarily
pass through the individual,” and might include “human groups, socio-economic
ensembles, data-processing machines, etc.” (p. 36). Hence, Guattari
(2000) looks at how the individual - understood as an assemblage - is produced
in and amongst these heterogeneous, partial, and entirely context-bound
‘components.’
This greater conceptual clarity is
deemed highly informative in the context of this discussion, in that it offers
a possible rapprochement between Blackman’s (2012) critical psychology
and Massumi’s (2002) affect theory. Henceforth, the mind might be dramatically
re-conceptualised as arising from within and between
assemblages of nonhuman and human bodies (Deleuze & Guattari,
2013). In fact, what Massumi
(2002) and Blackman (2012) do have in common, is that they view the mind as a
process. If such a conceptualisation
were to be adopted within a new process-based psychological paradigm,
researchers and practitioners could begin to conceive of life (human and
nonhuman) in terms of situated ‘becomings’; that is,
as part of “an ongoing dynamic process of response, interaction, adjustment,
orientation and – most importantly – sense” (Colebrook, 2011, p. 20).
Coming to our senses: dancing with Serres
Consciousness
belongs to those singular moments when the body is tangential to itself.
—Michel Serres
Critical to any proposed reinvention of
Psychology along the aforementioned lines, is the
realization that both Massumi (2002) and Blackman’s
(2012) respective approaches trouble any clear-cut distinction between the
‘inside’ and the ‘outside’ of the body.
In fact, within such process-oriented frameworks the mind, body, and its
environment are best understood as intrinsically related due to the fact they
these assemblages are always found alongside one another (Guattari,
2000). This nuanced conceptualization,
which flatly refutes Psychology’s ardent Cartesian dualism, is also evidenced
by Michel Serres’ (2016), The Five Senses. Here, this philosopher professes a Lacanian
perspective as to the genesis of subjectivity in stating that “Klein bottles
are a model of identity” (p. 22). For Serres (2016), a body has neither an inside nor an outside:
only a mingling mediated by the skin, which “intervenes in the things of the
world and brings about their mingling” (p. 97).
In this view, the body and soul are “inextricably” blended on the
surface of the skin, where they refuse to congeal into “a separate subject and
object,” even when “two mingled bodies” touch (Serres,
2016, pp. 25-26). In fact, it is events
like this which are the be-all and end-all of existence: “We only ever
experience mixtures, we encounter only meetings” (Serres,
2016, p. 28). Notably, this contention
runs completely at odds with Psychology’s separation of mind and body, and as
such, can counter this disciplines’ seemingly inexorable mind-body
dualism. Indeed, for Serres
(2016), such a neat Cartesian split is not only an impossibility, but a
travesty.
So, like Blackman (2012) and Massumi (2002), Serres advocates
a processual view of the body and soul/mind, in emphasizing “movement rather
than stable forms of fleshy matter” (Tucker & Goodings,
2014, p. 58). Further, he
enthusiastically asserts that: “a body is not born until it has danced” (Serres, 2016, p. 323).
Within this purview, bodies “shimmer like watered silk” (Serres, 2016, p. 25).
The implication of this Bergson-esque insight
is that because a body is nothing but movement, the mind is invariably also
taken along ‘for the ride.’ By way of
illustration, Serres (2016) describes how caressing a
localized area of one’s own body produces the self: “I touch one of my lips
with my middle finger. Consciousness resides in this contact” (p. 22). The point being that any attempts to separate
mind and body from each other, or their embeddedness is, not only an
impossibility, but is also a futile endeavour. Like Blackman (2012), Serres’
(2016) thinking also involves recourse to bodily attunement(s). As such, both of these
perspectives’ emphasis on entangled, or intermingled, mind-body relations might
inform the makings of the novel process-based Psychology advocated by this
article.
Further uses for Serres’ (1982) thinking within Psychology are revealed in
his book, The Parasite. Here, he
observes how, in the modern world, sensory, embodied experiences have become
obfuscated to the extent that existence itself has is
now geared toward language-based practices and the acquisition of information,
and nothing else: “They are all, nowadays, so exhausted, so saturated, so
hagridden with discourse, language, writing” (Serres,
1982, p. 40). Intriguingly, for Serres (1982), parasites (used here in a non-pejorative
sense) are “more or less” the cornerstone of “our environment” (p. 10). And for him, ‘noise’ is the “ultimate
parasite” (Serres, 1982, p. 4) between any two
systems. A feature of every single
relation (and space); ‘noise’ is everywhere and nowhere, and as such, is “both a vector and a parasite” (Serres, 1995, p. 58).
Here, what counts as ‘noise’ is said to be entirely dependent upon “the
position of the observer” (Brown & Stenner, 2009, p. 48). This is because in order
for a signal to be sent from one system to another, “noise must be
excluded, which means that this exclusion of noise is essential to the system
in the sense that it is constitutive of it” (Brown & Stenner, 2009, p.
48). Ergo, one can conclude that:
“Relation is non-relation” (Serres, 1982, p.
79). In Serrian
philosophy, all change (note
the influence of process philosophy here) is thereby said to occur at
“the boundary between two-systems that is made permeable by the noise-signal
interruption” (Brown & Stenner, 2009, p. 49).
The ramifications of integrating Serrian philosophy within any new process-based approaches
to psychological phenomena are, I contend, (at least) threefold. Firstly, because the mind and the body emerge
through contact with the skin’s surfaces it is these “events and singularities”
(Serres, 2016, p. 60) that Psychology should pay much
closer attention to. So instead of
conducting ‘traditional’ empirical work which examines how, as a hypothetical
instance, social media affects one’s thinking (in a seemingly straightforward
causal way); one might enquire as to how screen fatigue might tire out one’s
body, sap one’s psychic energy, and alter one’s relationship to the contexts in
which one is uniquely situated. As a
result of this integrated approach, psychologists might follow Serres’ lead and chart the trajectories of these “sensory
bodies” (Tucker & Goodings, 2014, p. 56) across
the different times and spaces of our lives.
Secondly, Serres’
emphasis on the haptic nature of existence, might spark psychological research
into the continual foldings of body into mind (and vice
versa), in such a way as to draw one’s attention to the former’s
“hemiplegic” (Connor, 2005, p. 155) orientation. Thus, bodies, and in theory, minds, are
conceived as pliable, and as such, always open to change. In this way, Serres’
(2016) thinking ties in neatly with both Blackman (2012) and Massumi’s (2002) own perspectives, regardless of whether
one places mind before body, or the reverse.
This is because what is ultimately being emphasized within Serres’ (2016) philosophy is the co-occurrence, and
therefore inseparability, of the soul and the body.
Lastly, Serres’
(1982) idiosyncratic and dark take as to the nature of our ecologies might
encourage psychologists to create sensory maps which chart the emergence of
localized parasites as they emerge so as to shape the
world around us. Most promising in this
respect, Serres’ (1982) work could act as a catalyst
for critically-informed psychological research into those experiences which are
induced by one’s everyday relations with other types of sensory, or sensing,
bodies – human and nonhuman (animals, technologies, etc.). As a consequence,
Psychology could begin to focus on “the creation and development of
unprecedented formations of subjectivity that have never been seen and never
felt” (Guattari, 1995, p. 91). Such a task would firstly demand that
researchers scrutinize the noise-signal relations as they occur within particular multiplicities, and give priority “to, the
background, to the sea of nothingness from which form emerges” (Clayton, 2012,
p. 34). Hopefully, Psychology can use Serrian philosophy to begin to pay closer attention to the
genesis of these aforementioned systems, and in the
process make an invaluable contribution toward a wider theoretical and
practical project which entails the development of “a new process-based
vocabulary for the way we conceptualize our senses” (Tucker & Goodings, 2014, p. 61).
Here, one might quip that Psychology as a discipline needs to become
less predictable in its desire to predict, because this only reifies, its
imaginary, and yet given, Cartesian ‘subject.’
Following the logic espoused across the entirety of this essay, to avoid
this mistake, Psychology as a subject specialism must jettison its
‘traditional’ concerns with subjects, objects, and spaces and cede priority to
“time and change” which are the “definitively central and salient metaphysical
issues” (Rescher, 2000, p. 3). As a result, this Psychology would become
concerned with “‘actio’ or ‘forming processes’”
(Stenner, 2017, p. 223) (following Alfred Schütz’s influence). Put emphatically, this paper has argued that
it will only be through the creation of a process-oriented Psychology that
pivots on the premise that experience is produced by ‘actual entities’
(Whitehead, 1978), ‘becomings’ (Deleuze & Guattari, 2013), or more plainly, events, that this
discipline can start to offer a better account of the increasing complexities
of life within this ever-changing modern world.
Conclusion
This paper has argued that if Psychology
can take inspiration from Blackman (2012), Massumi
(2002), and Serres’ (2016) concerns with different
kinds of corporeal and incorporeal bodies, it would be more able to provide an
integrative, non-reductive understanding of the inextricable relations which
exist between our bodies and minds.
However, any attempt to retain either the primacy or the existence of
the ‘thinking’ subject within this new model would be regarded as a conceptual
error, given that such a position would reify and re-affirm something which
does not exist. Instead, it was
suggested that critically-minded psychologists could
utilize insights taken from these process philosophies so as to map
ecologically-situated bodies (affects) of all kinds (Deleuze & Guattari, 2013).
Indeed, this article proposed that if Psychology used insights taken
from these onto-relational process philosophies, it might produce a radically
alternative means to describe those immanent external relations which produce
our ongoing experiences of life - without having to give recourse to the fictious
transcendent human ‘subject.’ If such
wholesale changes were to occur, this essay predicted that this discipline
would become much more capable of explicating how today’s rapidly fluctuating
multi-sensory environments affect our ongoing experiences of both self and
other.
an
international and interdisciplinary journal of postmodern cultural sound, text and image
Volume 18, Summer 2021, ISSN 1552-5112
References
Bateson, G. (1979). Mind
and Nature: A Necessary Unity. New York: E.P. Dutton.
Blackman, L. (2001). Hearing
Voices: Embodiment and Experience. London & New York: Free Association Books.
Blackman, L. (2012). Immaterial
Bodies: Affect, Embodiment, Mediation. Los Angeles,
London, New Delhi, Singapore & Washington, DC: SAGE.
Brown, S. (2012). Between the planes: Deleuze and social
science. In C.B. Jensen & K. Rodje (Eds.), Deleuzian intersections: science, technology,
anthropology (pp. 101-120). New
York: Berghahn Books.
Brown, S.D. (2018). Deleuze, Spinoza and Psychology: Notes
Towards An ‘Experience Ecology’. In M. Nichterlein
(Ed.), Putting the Deleuzian Machine to Work in Psychology. Annual Review of Critical Psychology, 14, 51-65.
Brown, D. S. & Stenner, P. (2009). Psychology Without Foundations: History, Philosophy and Psychosocial
Theory. Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, Singapore
& Washington DC: SAGE.
Clayton, K. (2012). Time Folded
and Crumpled: Time, History, Self-Organization and the Methodology of Michel Serres. In B. Herzogenrath (Ed.), Time and History in Deleuze and Serres (pp. 31-50). London & New York: Continuum.
Colebrook, C. (2011). Time and Autopoiesis: The Organism
Has No Future. In L. Guillaume & J. Hughes (Eds.), Deleuze and the Body
(pp. 9-28). Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
Connor, S. (2005). Michel Serres’s
Les Cinq Sens. In N. Abbas (Ed.), Mapping Michel Serres (pp. 153-169). Ann
Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.
DeLanda, M. (2006). A New Philosophy of Society: Assemblage
Theory and Social Complexity. London & New York: Continuum.
Deleuze, G. (1995). Negotiations:
1972-1990 (M. Joughin, Trans.). New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G. (2006). The Brain Is The
Screen. In D. Lapoujade (Ed.), Two Regimes of
Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975-1995 (pp. 282-291). New York & Los Angeles: Semiotext(e).
Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F.
(1994). What is Philosophy? (H.
Tomlinson & G. Burchill, Trans.). London & New York: Verso.
Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F.
(2013). A Thousand Plateaus (B. Massumi, Trans.). London
& New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
Freud, S. (2011). The Ego and the Id (J. Riviere,
Trans.). Mansfield Centre, CT: Martino Publishing.
Guattari, F. (1995a). Chaosmosis: an ethico-aesthetic paradigm (P. Bains
& J. Pefanis, Trans.). Bloomington
& Indiana: Indiana University Press.
Guattari, F. (2000). The Three Ecologies (I. Pindar & P. Sutton, Trans.). London &
New Brunswick, NJ: The Athlone Press.
Hayles, N.K. (2017). Hyper and Deep Attention:
The Generational Divide in Cognitive Modes, Profession,
187-199.
Massumi, B. (2002). Parables for the virtual: Movement, affect, sensation. Durham: Duke
University Press Books.
McHenry, L. B. (1995). Whitehead’s Panpsychism as the
Subjectivity of Prehension. Process Studies, 1 (24), 1-14.
Nichterlein, M. (2018). Putting the Deleuzian Machine to Work in Psychology: Critical and Clinical Becomings.
In M. Nichterlein (Ed.). (2018). Putting the Deleuzian Machine to Work in Psychology. Annual Review of Critical Psychology, 14, 7- 17.
Nichterlein, M. & Morss,
J.R. (2017). Deleuze and Psychology:
Philosophical provocations to psychological practices. London and New York:
Routledge.
Nietzsche, F. (2006). On the Genealogy of Morality (C. Diethe, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Protevi, J. (2011). Larval Subjects, Autonomous
Systems and E. Coli Chemotaxis. In L.
Guillaume & J. Hughes (Eds.), Deleuze and the Body (pp. 29-52). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Rescher, N. (2000). Process Philosophy: A
Survey of Basic Issues. Pittsburgh: University
of Pittsburgh Press.
Serres, M. (1982). The Parasite (L. R. Schehr, Trans.).
Baltimore & London: The John Hopkins University Press.
Serres, M. (2016). The Five Senses: A Philosophy of Mingled Bodies (M. Sankey & P. Cowley, Trans.).
London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Simondon, G. (1992). The Genesis of the
Individual (M. Cohen & S. Kwinter, Trans.). In J. Crary
& S. Kwinter (Eds.), Incorporations (pp. 297-319). New York: MIT Press.
Stenner, P. (2017). Liminality
and experience: a transdisciplinary approach to the psychosocial.
Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.
Tucker, I. & Goodings, L.
(2014). Sensing Bodies and Digitally Mediated Distress: Serres,
Simondon, and Social Media. The Sense & Society, 9 (1), 55-71. doi:
10.2752/174589314X13834112761047
Whitehead, A.N. (1978) Process
and Reality (Corrected ed.) (D.R.
Griffin & D.W. Sherburne, Eds.). New York: Free Press.